In an authority argument, the fact that someone
makes a statement is held to logically support the claim that that
statement is true. Let's just look at a few authority arguments.
1. Dinosaurs were
still around when humans first walked the earth. That's what my
grandpa says, and he's really old
2. The Hitlerage
Institute recently announced that critical thinking will destroy
society as we know it.
3. How can you say cat
juggling is okay? Everyone I know says that juggling is the worst
thing you can do to a cat!
4. Dragons are real.
You can trust me on this one.
5. A bum on the street
told me that monkeys really can fly, so we should all wear hats.
6. The state
department recently announced that Saddam Hussein was a transvestite.
Exercise 2.1. Try to figure out what all the above
arguments have in common before you read my description
of what makes something an authority argument. (My answer can be found
at the end of this chapter.)
Now, none of the following arguments are authority arguments.
7. A horse is like a
hippogriff. Hippogriffs can fly, so horses can fly.
8. Handgun Control,
Inc. faked statistics on gun violence. That proves all gun-control
activists are liars.
9. Statistics show
that once people start using a sunscreen, they almost never go back to
sunbathing without it, so sunscreen use causes dependence on
sunscreen!
10. If 100-mpg
carburetors existed, someone would have put them into production.
No-one has, so they don't exist.
11. Dogpatch community
college should not require a freshman writing course. For god's sake,
Harvard doesn't require freshman writing!
12. A recent study
shows that pelagic fish like Mozart better than Beethoven.
13. People of
different religions are always fighting each other, so we shouldn't
let those Presbetarians move in next door. They're nice, but the fact
that we're Quakers means we won't be able to avoid getting into fights
with them!
14. There must be a
magic cheese fairy. Where you think all that cheese comes from?
15. The dead man has
defensive wounds to both his hands, so I don't believe your claim that
he was lunging at you with a red-hot radioactive chainsaw when you
stabbed him.
Exercise 2.2. What do all of the above arguments have
in common that makes them not authority arguments
If we evaluate an argument by looking closely at the source of a
statement, it's an authority argument. If the best way to evaluate a
particular argument does not include looking at the
characteristics of a person or group, then it’s is not an authority
argument.
Exercise 2.3. Examine these arguments and identify all
the authority arguments. For each authority argument, write
out why it is an authority argument. For each non-authority
argument, write out how that argument is supposed to work
16. The USDA
classifies horses as flying mammals, so horses can fly.
17. Saddam has been
seen in a cocktail dress, a string bikini, and a Raggedy Ann costume,
so he's a transvestite.
18. Flush Limburger
says that all gun-control activists are liars.
19. 95% of Canadian
monkeys can fly, so all monkeys can fly.
20. The Republican
Party announced that providing sunscreen to children only causes
dependence on sunscreen.
21. Scientists working
for the oil industry claim to have proved that a 100 mile per gallon
carburetor is impossible.
22. The San Diego zoo
has a fire-breathing dragon, and the New York zoo has two of them, so
dragons really exist.
23. Dogpatch College
associated students Union insists Dogpatch College does not need a
freshman writing class.
24. Namor, Prince of
Atlantis, says that pelagic fish like Beethoven much less than they
like Mozart.
25. Cat juggling has
been shown to give cats whiplash, motion sickness and colliwobbles. So
it is really bad for cats.
26. The Pope says that
Presbyterians are dangerous because they're always starting fights
with Quakers.
27. Training people to
think for themselves is just like training people to be terrorists.
28. President Bush
says there’s a magic cheese fairy, which is why he will never declare
war on Wisconsin.
29. A fossil
Tyrannosaurus was recently found to have a fossilized human being in
its stomach. The human was carrying
a Betamax VCR and an eight track stereo, proving that he was eaten at
the very dawn of human history.
30. The entire Mormon
Tabernacle choir saw you stab that man, and they all say that he was
not lunging at you with a
red-hot radioactive chainsaw at the time.
How Authority Arguments Work.
We use authority arguments because there are circumstances where it is
safe to assume that someone else has already done all the critical
thinking necessary to determine the right answer. When we accept an
authority argument, we are assuming two things. First, we are assuming
that the person cited as an "authority" is in fact capable of doing all
of the research and critical thinking necessary to determine the right
answer to this particular question. Second, we are assuming that the
only considerations that influenced this "authority" were the totality
of the available evidence, and honest, conscientious reasoning from that
evidence. Authority arguments hold force because there are people who
take the time and effort necessary to deeply understand particular
subjects, and these people are usually willing to share the results of
their efforts with the rest of us. There are many people who make their
livings by providing the best possible information. Besides the fact
that most experts have a strong sense of professional integrity, they
also have a strong interest in being right, because they can lose income
and prestige if they are shown to be wrong.
How Authority Arguments Go Wrong.
If we don't have a strong reason to think that the "authority" has based
his statement purely on his own competent and thorough research and
critical thinking, then we should not take his word for anything. It
might happen that the "authority" simply does not have the right
expertise for this issue. Or it might happen that we have reason to
think that the "authority" is consciously or unconsciously motivated by
something other than a sense of professional responsibility in this
particular issue.
How To Think About Authority Arguments
An argument from authority can only have persuasive force when something
being said by that particular person or institution gives us good reason
to think that there is another argument - maybe a difficult or
complicated one - but definitely a logically compelling argument, for
that same thing. Thus "Fred says that..." or "The Fred Institute says...
" can only be taken as an argument if it is taken to mean "Fred (or The
Fred Institute) is known to do unbiased, competent research using good
logic and methodology, and has researched this topic thoroughly,
carefully and competently, and has critically analyzed and evaluated all
relevant arguments, and based on this research and reasoning, and has
honestly, and without conscious or unconscious bias concluded that... "
Critiquing authority arguments can get pretty complicated, so I’m going
to start off by identifying three kinds of specific reasons we might
have to think that some authority has not properly used her expertise,
as well as another kind of reason that might lead us to think that we
cannot rely on experts at all in some particular case.
1. If the authority in question has a demonstrably bad track record for
this kind of claim, that kills the authority argument. If his track
record is bad, he's no authority.
2. Professional qualifications or training can give someone authority if
her track record is unknown. But if she has the wrong kind of expertise
for this question, then she's no authority, because wrong expertise is
as bad as no expertise. So if the authority in question demonstrably
lacks the right qualifications, and has no proven good track record,
then the argument is no good.
3. If the authority has the right expertise and/or a good track record,
he might still be unconsciously (or consciously) influenced by some
material interest. If we don't know of any material interest in the
case, we should assume there is none, but if we do know that the
authority has some definite, proven, material interest in people
believing his conclusion, the argument is no good. He might honestly
believe in his statements, but he might also be influenced by that known
material interest, so he cannot be treated as an authority in this case.
The above considerations can undermine an authority even if she is the only
person currently put forth as an expert in this particular field. In
contrast, the following consideration basically knocks the whole idea of
using authority out of the window.
If a purported expert has a history of being off the mark, if she has
the wrong expertise, or if she has a material interest in this
particular question, we should have serious doubt that she’s
appropriately using the right expertise for this question. But
opposition by another properly qualified authority does not give us any
specific reason to think that the first expert might not be properly
using the right expertise. After all, it could be that the opposing
expert is the one screwing up. However, one of these experts must
be wrong, and it could be the first one, so we still can’t
take her word for it.
Track Record
The best way to prove that a person or institution has expertise is by
citing a long-term track record of accurate pronouncements. If a person
has turned out to be right over and over again, then that person is an
expert, period. If a person has a good track record on a particular kind
of issue, and we don't have any particular reason to doubt her word on
this particular issue, then her word is definitely good,
whether or not she has any formal training. (There are situations in
which we would doubt the word of someone with a good track record, but
we will discuss those later.) Remember, authority arguments are based on
the assumption that the "authority" is using some effective method of
figuring out answers to this kind of question. The only way to really
figure out whether or not a method really works is to try it a lot and
see what happens, so a good track record is the best proof possible that
the authority is using a method that works. Conversely, a bad track
record is all the proof anyone needs that someone is using a bad method.
A person can be festooned with degrees, certificates and awards, but if
he has a poor track record for accuracy, he has no authority whatsoever.
As long as we don't have any special reason to question Louis Ville's
judgment in this particular instance, the following is a very good
authority argument.
Louis Ville says that
Ding Bat's batting average in 1908 was 0.397215. Louis has been
telling me stuff like this about baseball for thirty years, and he's
always turned out to be exactly right.
But the following is a bad argument.
Well, it's true I've
been wrong every time so far, but I've studied this subject more
deeply than anyone else in history, and I hold several advanced
degrees in the subject, so you can be sure I'm right this time.
Now, which of the following is the best critique of
this bad argument?
1. The speaker can't be relied upon because he's not a proper expert.
His qualifications don't count because they don't matter here.
2. The speaker should not be trusted because he has a history of being
wrong. Even if he is as qualified as he claims, we should still discount
the claims of someone who has a bad track record, and this speaker
definitely has a bad track record.
Notice that critique two mentioned the crucial fact
that the arguer has a bad track record, and gave the logical
rule that says what we should do with "authorities" that have
bad track records. Good critiques tend to include mention of crucial
facts and logical rules.
One word of warning. A history of agreeing with your personal views does
not count as a good track record. Consider Connie.
Connie reads and listens to Flush Limburger, Dill O'Slimy and Schmuck
Dimwitty. None of these guys knows his posterior from a hole in the
ground, but Connie believes every word they say because they make Connie
feel that she's smarter and better informed than other people. Connie
particularly likes it when her favorite authors disparage people she
disagrees with. Logic and evidence are actively avoided because, quite
frankly, the slightest attention to logic and evidence will reveal
Connie and her favorite authors as morons. Now, even though everyone
here has a track record that is pathetic to say the least, Connie firmly
believes that each of these authors has an outstanding track record
because every time each one of them has said anything, Connie has agreed
vehemently.
Similarly, a history of disagreeing with you doesn't
make for a bad track record. Imagine that back in the Reagan Presidency,
when Saddam Hussein was at his most murderous, the following
conversation had taken place.
Laurel: West Asia Eyeball just
issued a devastating report on President Reagan's friend Saddam
Hussein. They say that Hussein has committed numerous human rights
abuses including summary detention, torture, assassination and use of
nerve gas agains civilians.
Camren: Yes, well, what would
you expect from an organization like WAE?
Laurel: What is do you mean? WAE
is the most respected eyeballing group in West asia!.
Camren: Oh please! Just look at
their record and you'll see that they don't deserve all that respect
at all.
Laurel: What's wrong with their
record? When have they ever been wrong?
Camren: You're so naive! Don't
you know that WAE has a long history of criticizing President Hussein?
Laurel: So what?.
Camren: And they've never
printed anything nice about him.
Laurel: Again, so what?
Camren: So they're obviously
biased! Why else would they print such horrible things about Saddam?
Laurel: Um, because he does
horrible things to people?
Camren: Now you're showing your
bias against Saddam. And WAE's bias means that we can ignore them too.
Now, which of the following is the best critique of
Camren's argument?
1. Camren doesn’t manage to come up with a single instance of WAE being
wrong about Hussein. Since he would presumably refute any WAE report he
can prove to be false, we can assume he hasn't found any he can refute,
which strongly suggests that there aren't any to find. This implies that
WAE has a good track record. The fact that they've produced an unbroken
series of bad reports on Saddam Hussein doesn't show any bias on their
part. It simply could be the case that Saddam is a total scumbag.
2. We can ignore Camren because he's wrong about WAE, and because Saddam
Hussein is a scumbag. WAE has produced a lot of reports showing that
he's a scumbag, and because he is a scumbag, we know that WAE isn't
biased.
Notice that number 1 gives crucial facts and logical rules, while number
2 does not mention either one of these things. Even worse, number 2
claims that WAE is accurate because Saddam Hussein really is a scumbag.
This is very bad, because the scumbagginess of Saddam Hussein is
precisely what Laurel is trying to prove. Since this is the point at
issue, it is only an opinion, not a fact, and so no one can use it as
evidence for some other claim.
Integrity
An important part of a person’s track record is his or her habitual way
of dealing with mistakes. Compare two well-known talk-show hosts. The
first host once falsely claimed that his previous show had one two Peabody
awards, when in fact it had won a single Polk award, and that
after he had left the show. The second host made public statements
excusing the behavior of a writer who had, for profit, exaggerated the
extent to which his “autobiographical” novel was based on fact.
Anyone can misremember, anyone can make a mistake, especially in the
heat of a live interview. The difference in integrity shows up in how a
person responds to people who point out his errors. The first host got
very angry with people who criticized him, saying that the difference
didn’t matter, and implying that his critics were being deliberately
unfair. The second host made a public retraction and apology. That’s
integrity.
Similar considerations apply to groups. Science, as a whole, has a
strong record of integrity because scientists tend to police their own
and each other’s mistakes. The history of science is littered with
claims that were once widely accepted but which are now generally
rejected. Adherence and enforcement of appropriate professional
standards is a vital part of expertise, and evidence that a group does not
police itself is evidence that that group should not be
treated as authoritative. I may be wrong about this, but it seems to me
that neither astrologers nor cereologists have ever retracted
any important claims. If an astrologer ever publicly claimed
that astrology had been ineffective in some particular case,
or that some particular astrological doctrine had been proved false,
that would strongly suggest that she at least had some integrity. If a
prominent cereologist publicly disagreed with the majority of his fellow
cereologists, and asserted that some famous crop-circle really could
have been made by humans, I would certainly acknowledge that he did not
lack integrity. Conversely, whenever a group has a track record of never
showing internal dissent, and never retracting claims, that group had
better clearly demonstrate s strong track record for accuracy before we
should take it seriously.
I think we should acknowledge integrity whenever it occurs, and
particularly in people with whom we disagree. I remember an account - in
a skeptical magazine - of a psychic who had written to newspapers
denouncing psychic hotlines for not taking the trouble to make sure that
all the operators they hired were real psychics. Unfortunately, the
skeptic who wrote the article I read used this only as an opportunity to
bash psychics, and thus failed to acknowledge the real integrity and
moral courage shown by the letter-writer.
Expertise
If you don't have a known track record for a particular person or
institution, you might be able to infer a track record based on the type
of person or institution involved. There is a strong presumption that a
recognized expert is very likely to be right so, in the absence of any
track record, (or other complication) we are justified in taking the
word of a recognized expert as an authority on his own subject.
Advertising agencies and public relations firms have a horrible track
record, so you should almost never take the unsupported word of an
advertising agency or a public relations firm. The same is true of
politicians. If you don't know a politician's track record for accuracy,
don't take his word for anything. Upon legal advice, I'm not saying
anything about lawyers. No sir, not one darn thing.
Expertise doesn't necessarily mean academic training. The school of hard
knocks can confer valid degrees also. A claim of expertise could be
backed up by university training, work experience, private research, or
some other kind of experience that has led to real knowledge in that
area. The key here is that we can generally assume that this person has
learned from her training and experience, simply because the vast
majority of people exposed to proper training and properly supervised
experience do learn from it. However, mere exposure to a
field doesn't confer expertise by itself. Prejudiced people, for
instance, can and will misinterpret what they see to accommodate their
prejudices. They can do this over and over again, each time becoming
more and more certain that their prejudices are being confirmed by
experience. A lifetime of this will produce a person who thinks he's an
expert, but who actually knows less than nothing about his subject. This
applies to distinguished professors just as well as to anyone else. The
difference is that a professor or similarly educated person is supposed
to have proved his expertise by demonstrating good reasoning and a good
track record in his subject. Therefore, in the absence of countervailing
reasons, we can take the word of an expert, such as a professor, or
someone who has done private research, as a good reason to believe what
he says. But beware, an expert is only an expert in his own field.
Outside of his own field, a professor is just a layman. Professors of
biochemistry are not necessarily authorities on biology, and vice versa.
As long as we don't have any reason to question their expertise, the
following are all good authority arguments.
Professor Val Ence,
who holds a doctorate in chemistry, says that "Aqua Regia" is a
combination of two different acids.
Ally Eska, who spent
20 years studying forests in Alaska, says the "peat moss" found there
is neither a peat nor a moss.
Every established
Physicist in the world believes that some version of Quantum Mechanics
will turn out to be correct.
The last argument is particularly strong, because the strongest possible
authority argument is one based on a consensus of known experts. If, for
instance, every biologist known to man believes that a certain
biological theory is correct, and we have no independent reason to
disagree or doubt their words, then that's an overwhelmingly good reason
to believe in that theory, even if everyone else on the planet
vehemently disagrees with it. But only the right expertise
counts. The following are all crappy arguments.
Professor Val Ence,
who is a doctor of chemistry, says that the "peat moss" found in
Alaska is neither a peat nor a moss.
Critique. The conclusion of this argument concerns
something found in Alaska. The right expertise for this kind of claim
would be Alaskan botany or perhaps Alaskan biology. Certainly, the right
kind of expert would be either a naturalist or someone who studies
Alaska, but we have no evidence that Professor Val Ence has ever studied
biology or Alaska. Since he's not the right kind of expert, we cannot
take his word on this issue.
Ally Eska, who has
spent 20 years studying the forests of Alaska, says Quantum Mechanics
will turn out to be correct.
Critique. Ally Eska has not been shown to be an expert
in physics, and only someone with expertise in theoretical physics will
be a reliable source on the issue of quantum mechanics, we should
discount what Ally Eska says about this matter.
Every established
Physicist in the world believes that "Aqua Regia" is a combination of
two different acids.
Critique. Aqua Regia is a matter of chemistry, not
physics. We have no reason to think that any of the world's established
physicists has any training or track record in chemistry,
so we can safely ignore this consensus.
No matter how much you know about chemistry, knowledge of chemistry will
never qualify you as an expert on Alaska. You can spend a lifetime
studying the forests of Alaska, and none of it will help you understand
quantum mechanics. Even if every established physicist in the world
believe some particular thing, their agreement is meaningless if it is
not a matter of physics.
Sometimes, determining whether or not an authority
has the right expertise can be kind of tricky. What is the right
expertise to determine whether or not astrology works, or whether or
not all crop circles are made by human pranksters? Generally,
biologists should be taken as authorities on biology, physicists as
authorities on physics, and so on, but astrologers and cereologists
cannot be taken as authorities on the effectiveness of astrology or
the non-human origin of crop circles. The reason for this
difference is simply that, for whatever reason, neither astrologers nor
cereologists do double-blind controlled studies. Neither do they take
any trouble to make sure that their claimed results are consistent with
established scientific results. The use of double-blind studies, and a
concern for consistency with science are important because they show a
strong desire to root out cases where people have been fooled
into believing a certain event has taken place, especially where such an
event is scientifically implausible. The bottom line here is that the right
expert is often the person who can look into a field from the outside
and tell whether it’s possible that the claimed results are due to
errors or trickery, or the person who can look at a claimed result and
tell whether or not established scientific results give us good reason
to think that it didn’t really happen. For this reason, a stage magician
is the right expert to tell us whether or not a claimed psychic could be
using trickery or an astrologer using cold reading to fool people, and
an astronomer or a physicist is the right expert to tell us whether or
not astrology or psychic powers are physically possible.
Finally, even the right expertise only counts when it is used.
The following is a very bad argument.
I'm sure that the
Indian King Ashoka was a Hindu. I mean, I'm only guessing. I've never
looked it up, but you can take my word for it because I'm an
established professor of Indian History.
Critique. This argument is bad because, no matter how
well established the professor is, his expertise only counts if he uses
it, and here he is clearly not using his expertise.
Expertise vs. Track Record
Basically, a known bad track record always trumps
expertise. When we don't have any messy complications, a recognized
expert with a good track record is about the best authority you can
get. However, a recognized expert with a bad track record is
absolutely useless.
We should trust Conn
T. Nental when he says that the Himalayan mountain range is not
getting any taller because, although he's usually been wrong when he
tells us things like this, he does hold a doctorate in Geology, with
an emphasis in Plate Tectonics and mountain formation, so we can take
his word for it.
Critique. Normally, we would think that a person with
these qualifications would be a reliable expert. However, we happen to
know that Conn T. Nental has a very poor track record, and a
poor track record always means that an authority is no good.
Advocacy and Authority
An “advocate” is a person who spend a significant portion of his time
trying to get other people to believe some particular thing. Like-minded
advocates often join together to create foundations, alliances and other
groups. GreenPeace and Mothers Against Drunk Driving are prominent
examples of such groups. Less famous groups might advocate for the
rights of the mentally ill, for the existence of earth-visiting aliens,
the non-human origin of crop-circles or the moral dangers of indoor
plumbing. The mere existence of such a group cannot make it (or any of
its members) into an authority, nor can an impressive letterhead, a
stunningly designed website or millions of adoring fans. The only
thing that can make such a group into an authority is a good track
record for accuracy. If the group’s press releases have overwhelmingly
turned out to be correct in all significant factual matters, then the
group should be considered a reliable authority. If the group’s
statements have frequently turned out to be importantly wrong on factual
matters, then they are not an authority, no matter how many members and
supporters they have.
Pseudo Authority
There are also a large number of people out there who was taken as
experts but who have not done the kind of research that would qualify
them as experts. These people are widely read, and widely taken as
authorities, just because because they tell people things they want to
hear. They write about esoteric subjects and so may be taken as an
expert by many people even if he or she has never applied appropriate
reasoning to his or her subject. Even worse, because of the public
popularity of bold and exciting claims about these subjects, people who
do not make such claims will not be popular with the public.
In such subjects, those who make exciting claims can be presumed to have
a strong interest in making those claims, and thus such an authority
should be discounted unless it can be shown that independent observers
have found him or her to have a strong track record for accuracy.
Interest
A person or institution has an interest when he has a strong
reason to prefer one side of a question to the other. People can be
consciously or unconsciously influenced by their material needs. So if
the expert in question has a personal reason to prefer one side over the
other, then we cannot take his unsupported word on that issue. On the
other hand, everyone has general interests. Cops make their
livings providing people who can be convicted of crimes, and so every
cop has a general interest in lying about what he saw the
suspect do, where he found the evidence and so on. But we can't say that
any particular cop has a significant reason to lie about any
particular suspect just because cops in general can gain
advantages by lying about suspects. Most people who can gain
advantages by lying still tend strongly towards telling the
truth, so a generalized reason for lying gives us no reason to
think that any particular person is lying at any particular
time. You can only say that someone has reason for
bias in this case when there is some provable feature
of his present situation that would predispose him to prefer that this specific
case came out one way rather than another.
I remember back when President Bush was preparing to invade Iraq I was
very impressed by the fact that the governments of both France and
Russia vgorously opposed the invasion. That is, I was impressed until I
found out that both France and Russia had massive investments in Iraq.
Now, it might have been true that they both opposed the war
because they honestly judged it to be unjustified and in violation of
international law based on their knowledge of the region and their
expertise in international affairs. But, on the other hand, they might
have been just looking to protect their investments, and it is this
latter possibility that means that we cannot take their unsupported word
for the illegitimacy of the Iraq invasion.
Remember it is only actual motives that can undermine an authority. If
someone had made an unsupported claim that France and Russia must
have investements in Iraq, that would not have been enough to
undermine their authority. It is only if it is proved that
they actually do have these investments that their authority
is undermined.
Interest vs. Expertise and Track Record
Interest trumps both track record and expertise. Even a recognized
expert with a good track record cannot be taken as an authority if his
pronouncements also substantially serve his own interests. If we know
that someone has a substantial interest in the position he is upholding,
then we probably shouldn't take his word for it. (The only exception
here might be if the speaker had a good track record that included a
history of making true statements that were against his own
interests. If a qualified speaker has proven that he would be willing to
tell the truth if the truth hurt him, we should probably be willing to
take his word when the truth helps him. Probably.)
Snot Rag tells us that
a pocket handkerchief is absolutely essential to maintaining good
respiratory health. Yeah, I know he's recently purchased shares in a
handkerchief factory, but he's got a long history of making accurate
statements about respiratory health issues, so he's bound to be right
this time.
Critique. Because of his track record, Snot Rag would
normally be considered an expert here, but we can’t take him as one
since his financial stake in the handkerchief factory might have
unconsciously influenced him to believe this claim about respiratory
health.
As a prominent and
well-respected physician with ten years of medical training and twenty
years of experience as a medical doctor, I've always said that vitamin
supplements were completely unnecessary for good health. Until now
that is. Yes, I've recently discovered that vitamin supplements are
completely vital to good health! Oh, and by the way, let me show you
my new book on the need for vitamin supplements and invite you to try
my new line of vitamin supplements, "Doctor Pan der Rer's Vitamin
Supplements for Good Health and the Avoidance of Painful, Lingering
Death."
Critique. Pan der Rer has a definite financial interest
in this issue, and widespread acceptance of what he says about vitamins
would lead to him making a lot of money. We don’t need to believe that
he’s deliberately lying, but it’s still reasonably possible that the
possibility of profit has influenced his judgment, so we can’t take his
word on this issue.
False Accusations of Bias.
You should however beware of people who claim someone is "biased"
because they have a general interest in the truth of the kind
of claim being advanced. There are many, many advocacy groups out there
who support themselves by selling books explaining their reasons for
boring us to tears with endless stories of boring atrocities and tedious
crimes against humanity. Just because these groups tend to get more
money whenever people believe their stories doesn't mean they have a
significant interest in lying. Many of these groups have excellent
track records, and on their track record is how they should be judged.
In fact, some of the best track records out there are held by advocacy
groups, so you can't discount the word of an advocacy group merely
because it's an advocacy group. Well-respected advocacy groups have
considerable authority, mainly because such groups only ever get the
respect of independent observers by being right over and over again. The
following is therefore a logically compelling argument.
Amnesia Intentional is
admired the world over for it's work combating the scourge of
absent-mindedness in high places. Recently, Amnesia Intentional issued
a report condemning the government of Mnemonia, which completely
forgot about over two thousand of its citizens for whole holiday
weekend.
And this is a bad argument.
You shouldn't trust
Amnesia Intentional's report on Mnemonia because Amnesia Intentional
is entirely supported by donations from people opposed to governmental
absent-mindedness. After all, if people didn't believe that some
governments are very forgetful, they'd never give money to Amnesia
Intentional.
Critique. If Amnesia Intentional has a good track
record, then you know it's usually been right even though it has always
had this general interest in promoting reports of forgetfulness.
Therefore that good track record is proof that Amnesia Intentional
generally ignores it's self-interest in these reports, and only reports
absent-mindedness in high places when it actually exists.
Remember, the rule is a good track record overrides a general interest
while a particular interest overrides a good track record.
Both arguments given in the following conversation are bad arguments.
Nestor. Now you have to admit
that all politicians are liars. Professor Cy Nick says so!
Jennifer. Rubbish! Professor Nai
Eve says that no politicians are liars, so you have to admit no
politician ever told a lie.
Nestor. Well, Cy Nick has been
studying politics for thirty years, so you have to believe him!
Jennifer. Nai Eve is a
distinguished professor of political science at a major university, so
she's gotta be right!
Nestor. Cy Nick has never been
wrong about politics, so he's right this time!
Jennifer. Nai Eve is a
world-renowned expert, so she's the one we should listen to!
Nestor. Cy Nick is
internationally famous too, so you should listen to him!
Jennifer. Oh yeah? Well Nai Eve
has been studying politics for just as long as Cy Nick, so she's the
expert here!
Nestor. That's a laugh! Well Cy
Nick also holds a distinguished professorship, so he's the expert, not
Nai Eve!
Jennifer. You know that Nai Eve
has never been wrong? Did you know that? Huh? Huh?
Critique. Both of these arguments are clearly bad, and
for the same reason. Given the fact that both of the experts described
here are fully qualified, have good track records and no known interest
in the matter, we would normally take both of them as authorities.
However, their expertise conflicts on this question, and the opposition
of each means that the other’s word cannot be taken here.
Experts are not oracles. Nothing is ever true
merely because some particular person or institution said it. What
experts have that the rest of us don't is prolonged access to the best
information and arguments available for their fields. They can use
that access to build up a knowledge base that they can share with the
rest of us. But we can only rely on that knowledge base when we are
sure that it exists and that what the expert says is based only on it.
If the "expert" is not an expert in the relevant field, if she is
biased, if her arguments have been discredited, if other experts
dispute her conclusion, or if there is credible contradictory evidence
already in play, then the appeal to her authority is fallacious. This
does not mean that we should ignore her. Given that she has some
expertise, she may be able to offer arguments in support of her
claims, and one or more of those arguments may turn out to be good,
even though her mere word carries no weight.
Exercise 2.4. For each of the situations described
below, determine whether we should take the word of that particular
person.
31. One person has no formal education in the relevant subject, but has
a long history of successfully answering difficult questions in that
subject. She has no interest in this particular question, and other
experts do not express disagreement with her on this question. Should we
accept her as an authority on this question?
32. Another person has extensive training, and has earned several
advanced degrees in this subject. However, many of her pronouncements in
this subject have turned out to be wrong. Should we accept her as an
authority on this question?
33. A third person has an excellent track record in this subject, but
her track record only concerns questions in which she has no particular
interest. The present question is one in which she does have a
particular interest. In fact, she stands to make a considerable amount
of money if people believe her answer to this question. Should we take
her as an authority on this particular question?
34. A fourth person has several advanced degrees in this subject, and is
widely recognized as an expert in this subject, but he has a particular
interest in this question, and stands to make a considerable profit if
we believe his answer. Should we take him as an authority on this
particular question?
35. A fifth person has advanced degrees in a different
subject. She has no known training or track record in this
subject. Should we take her as an authority on this question?
36. A sixth person has a very good track record in a different
subject. She has no known training or track record in this
subject. Should we take her as an authority on this question?
37. A seventh person is a well-respected authority in this particular
subject. We don't know her track record, but none of her opponents have
come up with any instance where she was clearly wrong before. She has no
particular interest in this subject, and none of the people who disagree
with her have qualifications that are even remotely comparable to hers.
Should we take her as an authority on this question?
38. An eighth person makes his living as an expert in this particular
subject. A lot of people accept him as an authority in this subject, and
take his word for things without checking elsewhere to see if he is
right. We don't know his track record, but he has no particular interest
in this question, and no qualified experts disagree with him. Should we
take him as an authority on this question?
39. A ninth person makes her living pointing out wrongdoing by a certain
group. Whenever she reports negative things about this group, her income
increases. Her answer to the present question constitutes a negative
claim about this particular group. She has no more interest in this
question than she has in any other question about this group, and all of
her previous negative claims about this group have turned out to be
true. Should we take her as an authority on this question?
40. A tenth person makes his living making negative claims about a
certain group. Whenever he reports negative things about this group, his
income increases. His arm to the present question constitutes a negative
claim about this particular group. He has no more interest in this
question than he has in any other question about the group, but at the
present time we do not know his track record on this type of claim, and
neither he nor anyone else can demonstrate that any of his previous
negative claims have turned out to be true. Should we take him to be an
authority on this question?
41. A twelth person has several advanced degrees in the subject, and is
a widely respected authority on the subject, and has no particular
interest in this question. However, at least one comparably qualified
expert on this subject is known to disagree with him on this question?
Should we take the first expert as an authority on this question?
Fallacies
Sometimes it is easy for a trained person to see that a particular
argument is a load of crap. This is because there are certain bad
arguments that are fairly often erroneously accepted as logically
compelling arguments by untrained and/or dishonest people. These crappy
but common "arguments" are technically called "fallacies." (Some people
use the word "fallacy" to mean some particular belief that they disagree
with. This is misleading, because one's disagreement with another's
belief cannot by itself mean that the other is doing anything logically
wrong by believing the disputed belief. And merely calling
something a fallacy doesn't make it false.) So, a fallacy is a type of
argument that is frequently taken to be a logically compelling argument,
even though it is actually always a bad argument. There are a large
number of fallacies, many of which are so common, or so interesting that
they have special names all of their own. Here I will talk about all of
the fallacies that might possibly be thought to be associated with
authority arguments.
False Authority
Broadly, an argument commits false authority when.
1. The person, group or institution making the claim clearly
has no substantial expertise in the topic under discussion. and/or
2. The person, group or institution making the claim clearly
has a bad track record on these kinds of claims. and/or
3. The person, group or institution making the claim clearly
has an interest in this issue.
If someone says that some authority supports his conclusion, but doesn't
tell us who that authority is, his conclusion isn't really
supported..
Scientists have proved that we only
use ten percent of our brains. (What scientists? When? How did
they prove this?)
Someone who isn't qualified in any way cannot be taken as an authority.
Protein based shampoos
have to use vegetable protein to work properly. I'm a poorly trained
retail clerk, so I should know!
Of course aliens are
abducting soap opera stars and replacing them with robots make of
toilet paper rolls glued together with expensive, french-milled soap.
Lux Flakes says so on his immensely popular website,
www.soaprobots.com.
I was the world’s top
actor for fifteen minutes back in the eighties, and you can take my
word for it that Bunkumology is the only true road to mental and
upper-colonic health!
Actually, if something’s only visible advocates are
celebrities, washed-up or otherwise, that’s a good sign that there’s
nothing to it.
And it's worse if that celebrity is being paid to ... um, "endorse” a
product.
You've got to believe
that the "Premauture Poverty Retirement Product" is the best available
retirement plan and won't eat up your savings leaving you homeless,
living under an overpass, freezing cold and so very, very alone. We've
hired some of the worlds best loved character actors to do our
commercials! You trust kindly-looking old character actors, don't you?
The wrong expertise is just as bad as no expertise at all.
We know that the
Pennsylvania legislature did not blackmail Washington into spending
the winter at Valley Forge because Professor Boon Doggle, a
distinguished professor of Biology says so.
Remember that a bad track record always kills authority stone dead.
The Freedomland
government insists that Draconia possessed weapons of mass digestion
and would have used them if Freedomland hadn't invaded Draconia. I
know that the Freedomland government was completely wrong when it
previously said that the Spammish government sunk the FLS Potato with
a giant potato-masher grenade, and they were wrong when they said that
the nation of North Tofu was completely unprovoked when it invaded
South Tofu, and they were lying through their teeth when they said
that the North Vermichellians fired underwater sausages at a
Freedomland Dessertship. In fact, the Freedomland government has never
been accurate in claims of this kind. But, they have always had
exactly the right kind of expertise to verify these kinds of claim, so
we can absolutely trust them this time.
Pronouncements by persons or institutions of a type that that's never
been reliable cannot be relied upon.
Shill and Knownothing,
the public relations firm, has announced that the Rummybuddies, (who
recently invaded Quseven) are committing atrocities against the
Qusevenis. It's true that public relations firms have a bad track
record in general, but Shill and Knownothing is a brand new company,
with new people, and therefore no track record, so you can trust them.
And, of course, a particular material interest ruins even the best
authority in that particular question
Skiffer Skillets are
the best! You can trust them because super-sou-chef
Emerlililililifobobobobob-bo-bop said they're absolutely the best
skillets in the world, just after he inherited the company that makes
Skiffer Skillets.
Finally, an expert who fails to actually use his expertise is just as
bad as someone who isn't an expert at all. Sometimes an expert claims
that, although there is no formal scientific research or other
independent evidence backing up his claim, we should accept it as
authoritative because it is based on his "trained intuition." The idea
here is that experts get so that they have a "feel" for their fields, so
that their guesses and gut feelings have the same force as those
pronouncements that are backed up by actual research. Unfortunately,
real research has shown that experts' "trained intuition" is no more
accurate than a lay person's "guess." In fact, trained intuition
actually lowers the performance of experts because they sometimes choose
to ignore their training in favor of a gut feeling. Despite what we see
in the movies, the gut never performs as well as training.
Based on my trained
intuition, I can confidently assert that this prisoner will break
parole by committing more crimes, and should therefore not be released
on parole.
The basic idea behind the false authority fallacy is that an arguer is
offering someone as an authority when we have clear reason not to take
that person as an authority. This is either because the person offered
hasn't been proved to be a qualified expert, or it is because we have
some particular reason to discount his opinion in this case.
Red Herring
The red herring fallacy occurs when someone tries to distract us with
something that isn’t really relevant to the issue at hand. I wouldn’t
even mention red herring in this chapter, except that there's an
interesting form of red herring associated with authority arguments. I
say "associated" because it actually has nothing to do with authority,
even though it tries very hard to pretend that it does. This is the use
of phrases like "but who are you to say" as attempts at refuting arguers
who have not given authority arguments.
Lee: We should believe that
badger bowling is morallly wrong because a lot of badgers get bruised,
and a lot of badger bowlers get bitten by badgers.
Alvin: But who are you to say
what's morally wrong? Who gave you the authority to condemn badger
bowling?
Notice that, even though Alvin is acting like Lee gave an
argument based on her own authority, Lee actually gave an argument based
on certain facts about badger bowling. Alvin's cry of "but who
are you to say" completely misses the point of Lee's argument. (That’s
what makes it a red herring.) The fact that Lee isn't established as an
authority isn’t relevant to the issue of whether or not
injuries to badgers and badger-bowlers justify banning badger bowling.
Thus Alvin commits a huge, and rather whiney, red herring.
Circular Argument
An argument is circular when questioning its dubious premise sooner or
later leads right back to the unsupported restatement of the conclusion.
(This can happen when someone attempts to save a question-begging
argument by coming up another question begging argument for that
question-begging premise. Keep doing that over and over, and you'll
eventually start to repeat yourself.) An argument can only work if its
premises are supported by existing, well-established knowledge, or by
premises that themselves are supported by existing, well-established
knowledge. An argument that attempts to support itself in mid air will
always fall.
I know Jeff is honest
because Marie insists that he is. And we can trust Marie because Rudy
swears that Marie is absolutely honest. As for Rudy, well, Jeff
insists that Rudy is absolutely reliable! (So the claim that
Jeff is honest ultimately rests on... the claim that Jeff is honest!)
We know that astrology
works because it has been validated by our best psychics. How do we
know that validation by these psychics can be trusted? Simply because
each of them has an astrological chart that indicates absolutely
stunning psychic ability. (So astrology tells us that
astrology is reliable.)
Benjamin. You should believe Rush
Limbaugh is a political expert because Ben Stein says he is.
Shaylee. But is Ben Stein a good
judge of political expertise?
Benjamin. Of course he's a good
judge of political expertise! Rush Limbaugh says he's a genius!
Circular arguments demonstrate the need for fact mining. Look for an
independently supported claim to authority in the above arguments. You
won't find one. Not of these people are shown to be authorities by
anything outside their circles, so none of their claims can be taken as
exidence for anyone's expertise.
Ad Populum
The fallacy of ad populum consists of thinking that something is true
merely because a lot of people think that it is true. This counts as an
authority argument because it relies on the credibility of a group of
people who just happen to believe something. But such arguments are
absolutely always bogus. The fact is that things that "everybody knows"
often turn out to be totally false, so popularity can never make a
belief true.
Jaren. Don't even try asking
old MacLir to contribute to your charity. He's Scottish, and everyone
knows that Scotsman are tight with money.
Perry. Hoots mon, dinna fash
y'self o'er yon haverin'!
Jaren. Come again?
Perry. Sorry. I meant to say
you're committing an ad populum.
Jaren. I'm coming a what?
Everybody knows that
chiropractic works!
Everybody knows that
we only use ten percent of our brains.
Everybody says that
whatever Fred says is true.
The united opinion of a million uninformed people are no better than the
opinion of a single uninformed person. When the only support a claim has
is the fact that "everybody knows" it's true, then it's not supported at
all.
Poisoning the Well
This is a crude but effective fallacy by which people are set up to
disbelieve in a source that they might otherwise find credible. This is
done by simply making disparaging .remarks about the source in question.
You can read the story
in the OC Weekly, if you're willing to wade through all that liberal
fog.
(Inspired by a column by Ann Coulter) In
other appeasement news, there was another peace march in Washington
today.
You're going to hear
that slippery two-faced human slime heap Henry Kissinger defend his
role in prolonging the Vietnam War? Well, make sure you keep an open
mind.
Liberalism is a mental
disorder. (I saw this on the back of an SUV in Orange County.)
The essence of this fallacy is that the speaker is trying to persuade us
to assume that some person or group of persons is unreliable without
giving any evidence that she is. Of course, if the speaker can come up
with legitimate examples of where the source has previously failed to
tell the truth, then it would follow that the source is unreliable. But
just throwing out a few insults won't cut it.
Ad Hominem
The fallacy of ad hominem is generally an attempt to discredit some
argument or refute some claim by pointing out something objectionable
about the person or institution who makes the claim. The objectionable
thing will be true, but it won't be the kind of thing that could
undermine the person or institution's authority. There's two ways to
commit ad hominem. First, by trying to prove a statement false
by pointing out some objectionable feature of some person who says that
the statement is true.
Rush Limbaugh says
that people have a prima facie right to own firearms. You know how
unreliable he is, so people don't have a prima facie right to own
firearms
Laura Schlessinger
says abstinence is the only absolutely guaranteed way of avoiding
pregnancy and STDs. She has no expertise in this area, so we know
abstinence is not the only absolutely guaranteed way of avoiding
pregnancy and STDs.
Now it's true that neither Rush nor Laura has any authority in these
fields, but all that means is that we can't use them as authorities. It
doesn't mean that what they say is false. The second way to commit ad
hominem is to try to undermine somebody's authority by pointing out some
objectionable, but irrelevant fact about that person.
Don't trust her. She
plays the bagpipes!
Remember that a track
record of producing nothing but negative reports isn't a bad track
record. A bad track record is only a history of producing unreliable
reports. The following is a terrible argument.
We shouldn't trust
William Shirer's report that Herr Hitler authorized the murder of
mentally ill Germans. Shirer has written many reports about Hitler,
and all of them have been negative. How can we trust such a biased
source?
Ad Hominem is often deployed in an attempt to undermine authorities. In
such a case, the arguer will bring up a negative fact about an authority
that has nothing whatsoever to do with whether or not he is using
appropriate expertise in this instance.
We can ignore
President Clinton's opinion on the budget. Didn't he lie about having
sex with a woman not his wife?
Just like in false authority, the ad hominem fallacy offers us reasons
that just aren't relevant to the issue.
If you're interested, the Fallacy of
Slander is actually a variant of Empty Explanation
because it attempts to "explain away" criticism or other inconvenient
information by inventing an unworthy motive and falsely
attributing it to the source of that criticism. appeal to
motives always fail because they never come with evidence that
supports the idea that the source has an unworthy motive. This
distinguishes them from counter arguments based on material
interest that always come with some kind of
factual evidence to back up the idea that the source might be
unduly infulenced by self-interest.
Sometimes, when people are contradicted by appropriate authority, they
respond by lashing out at the authority that contradicts them by accusing
that authority of having an unworthy motive or a material interest. They
do this based solely on the fact that the authority contradicts them,
and thus put forward absolutely no evidence to support the accusation.
The legal term for making such an unsupported accusation is "slander",
so I refer to this sort of thing as the "fallacy of slander." For
example:
Of course those
scientists don't believe I have psychic powers. They're all driven by
fear.
This is a fallacy because the speaker doesn't give us any reason to
think that scientists are afraid of anything. He's just pulling this
claim out of his ... out of thin air. (And it should be clear that
anyone who disagrees with the speaker about his possession of psychic
powers will also disagree with him about the scientists who think he
doesn't have psychic powers, so this is a presumption fallacy)
So what if Valerie
Vaughn says that there's published scientific papers in support of
Astrology. That just proves that she wants to make money out of
Astrology.
How does the speaker know what Vaughn's motives are? He doesn't want to
deal with the possibility that those papers really exist, so he tells a
slimy lie about Vaughn to distract people from the real issue. Again,
the people who cite Vaughn as an authority would deny that she's
influenced by a desire for profit, so the speaker here has to prove it.
He can't just say it.
How do we know that
the left hates America? Just look at the fact that the left is against
the war! They're against the war because, as usual, they cannot put
aside their hatred of America.
This argument is about the clearest example of dishonesty and moral
cowardice that I can think of. The speaker is absolutely refusing to
acknowledge the possibility that a reasonable person could
disagree with him, (let alone the possibility that the war is a bad
thing), so he makes up an imaginary motive, with no support whatsoever,
and sneeringly attributes it to his opponents.
The essence of this fallacy is that the speaker wants us to believe that
the person they're attacking has an unworthy motive without offering us
any REAL evidence that they possess such a motive. It's true that these
idiots think that the fact that speaker is expressing a particular
opinion is "evidence" that he or she has a material interest in people
believing that opinion, but that's complete nonsense.
Fallacy of slander is different from the legitimate tactic of referring
to real independent evidence that an arguer has a particular
interest in that the speaker either makes unsupported
accusations of hidden motives, or refers vaguely to some general
interest.
Remember, if the arguer gives you actual evidence that
the speaker has a specific interest, it's not fallacy of slander.
If the arguer's only "evidence" is just the speaker's opinion,
it's fallacy of slander.
Note that the only fact in such an argument is that the
authority could have the interest or motive ascribed to him.
But absolutely every authority ever cited could have a secret
material interest or vicious motive for saying what he says. Fallacy of
slander wants us to disregard an authority merely because is could
be true that he has a bad motive. If this works, we should
disregard all authorities.
This fallacy is generally resorted to by people who cannot even begin to
deal with the arguments offered by their opponents. Instead of thinking
about the actual arguments, they make up phony "explanations" for the
fact that their opponents are saying what they are saying, and then
pretend that these are the real reasons why their opponents think what
they think. Whether this fallacy is committed deliberately or
unconsciously makes no difference. It is profoundly dishonest either
way.
Phony Refutation
This fallacy occurs when someone attacks an arguer's behavior instead
of her argument in a case where her argument is not based on her
own authority.
This fallacy occurs when someone claims to refute someone else's argument
based on evidence that the other person isn't sincere.
This is based on a reasonable rule of thumb, but it's a fallacy
nevertheless. The fact is, we rely a lot on what other people tell us,
so evidence that somone is insincere gives us good reason to distrust
his testimony. Would you believe a Captain who told you "The ship's in
no danger. Everything's fine!" as he frantically climbed into the only
lifeboat? But the fact that he's abandoning ship only means that he
thinks the ship is in trouble. We would only think that it really is in
trouble to the extent that we think this particular Captain is an expert
on this ship. If we knew he was crazy from Dengue Fever, for instance,
his insincere assurances would not alarm us. Similarly, when someone's
behavior belies her statements, all we can conclude is that she doesn't
believe what she's saying. We can't conclude that her insincerity proves
anything about her arguments. Consider this conversation.
Vicky. You know, animals have
feelings and desires, feel pain and they deserve their lives for the
same reasons that people do, so it really is immoral to cut up living
creatures to make clothes.
Nell. Then why are you wearing
a red leather wedding gown? Obviously, using animals for clothes is
okay.
Who commits the fallacy here? Think about which of these two people
gives relevant reasons for her opinion, and which cites a reason that
has nothing to do with the real issue? (Many students get this one
exactly backwards, even after several lectures on the subject!)
Now, if you take the time to do a little fact mining, and base your
opinion on the facts, the issue becomes easier.
Facts:
1. Animals have feelings.
2. Animals have desires.
3. Animals feel pain.
4. Vicky is wearing a red leather wedding dress.
These facts cannot add up to a conclusion that cutting up animals for
clothes is morally okay. Fact number 4 does not contradict facts 1
through 3, and Vicky's argument is based entirely on those facts. Vicky
does not give an authority argument. We would
tend to disbelieve an authority who does not herself believe what she's
saying. The fallacy here is in taking that insincerity as refuting non-authority
arguments. This is like our first example of red herring, in that the
person committing the fallacy treats a non-authority argument
as though it were an authority argument.
Fallacy Recap.
If you are really, really, really sure you understand all the fallacies
described above, you can skip this section and the one after it, and
goes straight to Exercise 2.5. This section gives a brief recap of the
fallacy definitions.
False authority is where an arguer relies on
someone who is either unqualified, or at least is clearly unreliable
in this instance.
Special pleading, in authority arguments, is when an arguer takes one
expert as authoratitive while ignoring the fact that other, equally
qualified experts disagree with the expert he likes.
Red herring is where an arguer refers to facts that really are not
relevant in this particular case, such as the fact that someone who is
giving a non-authority argument is himself not an authority on this
issue.
Circular argument is where an arguer gives two or more mutually
supporting "arguments" without providing proper independent support for
any of them.
Ad Populum is where an arguer thinks the common belief is the same as
having a properly qualified, independent authority.
Poisoning The Well is where an arguer derides a particular authority
without giving any particular reason to question that authority's track
record, qualifications or independence.
Ad Hominem is where an arguer attacks an authority by mentioning a true,
but irrelevant fact about that authority.
Fallacy of slander is where an arguer "explains" something an authority
says that by making an unsupported claim that the authority has a hidden
motive to say that that thing.
In Phony Refutation an arguer attacks an argument by giving
true reasons why the person giving the argument might be
insincere.
Fallacy Exclusion Rules.
Here’s how to tell when a bad argument isn’t committing some
particular fallacy.
False
Authority
If the argument does not cite someone as an authority, the fallacy
cannot be false authority.
If there is no bad track record, lack of qualification, or specific
interest, the fallacy is not false authority.
Special Pleading
If there is no equally qualified second authority, the
fallacy cannot be special pleading.
Red
Herring
If there is no documentable fact cited, the fallacy is not red herring.
If the fact given is actually relevant, the fallacy is not red herring.
Circular
Argument
If the doubtful authority is not supported by another doubtful
authority, the fallacy is not circular argument.
Ad
Populum
If any specific authority is mentioned, then the fallacy is
not ad populum.
Poisoning the
Well
If the arguer is not trying to knock down some specific authority, the
fallacy is not poisoning the well.
If any specific reason is given to doubt the authority, the
fallacy is not poisoning the well.
Ad
Hominem
If the argument attacked is not an authority argument, the fallacy is
not ad hominem.
If the reason given is not a supported claim of fact about the
authority, the fallacy is not ad hominem.
If the fact given is actually relevant to the authority, the fallacy. if
any, is not ad hominem.
Fallacy of slander
If the argument attacked is not an authority argument, the fallacy is
not fallacy of slander.
If the negative claim about the authority is actually supported by
facts, then the fallacy is not fallacy of slander.
If the motive mentioned would not be relevant to the authority, the
fallacy is not fallacy of slander.
Phony Refutation
If the attacked authority actually is cited in the attacked argument,
then the fallacy is not phony refutation.
If it does not attack the credentials of the person giving the argument,
then it is not phony refutation.
6 Ridiculous History Myths (cracked.com)
The best thing about authority arguments you can read right now is this this piece by Paul Krugman in the New York Times.
Julius Geldhof found me this excellent little TED ED video: How do you know whom to trust? - Ram Neta
Exercise 2.5. Name that
fallacy. Each of the following paragraphs is a description of an
argument that commits some particular fallacy. For each paragraph, name
the particular fallacy committed. If the fallacy committed is false
authority, add one of the modifiers "bad track record," "no relevant
expertise" or "particular interest" to your answer depending on
precisely what is wrong with that particular type of argument.
43. The argument aims at refuting some other argument, and is only based
on real evidence that the person making the other argument does not
really believe the conclusion of that argument.
44. The argument is based on the authority of an expert with an almost
unbroken history of being right about this kind of thing, but it is
known that another expert, whose history of being right is just as
impressive, disagrees with the first expert.
45. The argument is aimed at undermining the authority of an expert
cited by someone else, and it does so by saying that the expert must be
biased because he has some secret agenda in making this claim, without
producing any independent evidence that the expert has this secret
agenda.
46. The argument is based on the authority of an expert who has never
before been wrong about this kind of claim, but this particular case is
different in that, for the first time, it is well-documented that this
particular expert has a private motive for us to believe his statements
that he did not have in any previous case.
47. The argument is aimed at undermining the authority of an expert
cited by someone else, and it tries to do so by pointing out a true fact
that engages our attention, but which does not actually have anything to
do with how the expert might be using his expertise.
48. The argument is based on the authority of a purported expert, but
there is no evidence that this "expert" has relevant training, or a good
track record, or anything else that would qualify him as an expert in
this case.
49. The argument is aimed at undermining the authority of an expert, and
does so by referring to the expert in contemptuous terms, or otherwise
saying it is not a proper expert, or is untrustworthy, without giving
any actual reason to think that the expert is not reliable.
50. The argument is based on the authority of someone who is only an
expert in some completely different and unrelated field from the one
that we are expected to take him as an expert in.
51. The argument is based only upon the fact that its conclusion is
widely believed by members of the general public.
52. The argument is based on the authority of someone who has a long
history of being wrong about this particular subject.
53. The argument is based on the authority of a person whose only claim
to expertise is that he is considered an expert by some other person,
and this other person's only claim to expertise is that he is considered
an expert by the very person whose authority he is supposed to be
certifying.
54. The argument is aimed at refuting another argument by pointing out
that the person giving the argument is not an authority, but that other
argument is not based on any claim to authority for that person.
Exercise 2.6. Name that fallacy, round two.
For the purposes of these exercises, let us say that Gear Head is an
automotive technology expert with a Ph.D. in mechanical engineering, a
Ph.D. in electrical engineering, a Ph.D. in automobile technology, and
while he was an undergraduate he received a felony conviction for
stealing a Bob's Big Boy statue from outside a Bob's Big Boy restaurant
and converting it into a high-performance automobile which he drove all
the way across the United States at an average speed of 102 mph..
Let us also say that Chain Smoker is a high school dropout who smokes
four packs of cigarettes a day.
Clear Cut insists that Tree Farm is a leading expert on forest ecology.
Tree Farm says that Chain Saw is a world-recognized authority on forest
ecology. Nobody else considers any of these guys experts on anything,
and none of them has documented training or successful track record on
forest ecology.
Horn Spammity is a well-known radio show host who is famous for making
numerous definite pronouncements on matters of morality, politics and
culture. Millions of people listen to his radio show and applauded his
comments, but people who take the trouble to check up on what he says
find out that he is almost invariably wrong about matters of morality,
politics and culture.
Toss Pot has a completely unknown background.
Eye Ball is an expert on eye surgery with impeccable qualifications and
an impressive track record. Until now, he has not stood to gain or lose
by anything he is said publicly about eye surgery. However, he recently
acquired a considerable number of shares in the company that holds the
patent to the "Jackhammer and Lemon Juice" method of surgical vision
correction.
And Drive Train is another automotive technology expert with
qualifications that are just about exactly as impressive as Gear Head's.
Drive Train has done studies on hydrogen fuel cell technology, and has
concluded that it would take at least 20 years to convert even 20% of
California's vehicles to run on hydrogen fuel cell technology.
Each of the following paragraphs is an argument that commits some
particular fallacy. For each paragraph, name the particular fallacy
committed. If the fallacy committed is false authority, add one of the
modifiers "bad track record," "no relevant expertise" or "particular
interest" to your answer depending on precisely what is wrong with that
argument.
55. Chain Smoker
points out that The New England Journal of Medicine has published
numerous unchallenged studies proving that smoking cigarettes
seriously raises the risk of emphysema, heart disease and cancer. But
can you really take this seriously, given that Chain Smoker smokes
four packs of cigarettes every single day?
56. Everyone should
support the new "Slash and Burn" plan for forest management. Clear Cut
says that this is the only environmentally sustainable forestry plan,
and he should know because Chain Saw says that Clear Cut is the
world's most reliable expert on forest ecology. And we know that Chain
Saw is an expert because Tree Farm says he is preeminent in the field.
And you know that Tree Farm is an expert because Clear Cut has said
many times that Tree Farm is one of the top men in the field.
57. Horn Spammity says
quite clearly and unequivocally that the banning of cigar smoking from
neonatal intensive care units is morally wrong, politically
reprehensible, and culturally bankrupt because it will inevitably lead
to the complete and utter destruction of Western civilization, and
perhaps the eventual destruction of the planet Earth itself.
58. Of course
McDonald's food is good for you. Everyone I know believes it's
wonderful!
59. Don't listen to
that idiot Gear Head when he talks about cars. Can't you see that he
doesn't know what he's talking about?
60. Toss Pot says that
marijuana smoking is absolutely immoral, so we should redouble our
efforts to prevent people from smoking marijuana.
61. We cannot listen
to Gear Head when he talks about engineering. Don't you know he has a
felony conviction?
62. You really should
consider the Jackhammer and Lemon Juice surgery to correct your
vision. Eye Ball is a leading expert on eye surgery, and he says it is
an amazing new breakthrough in vision correction surgery.
63. You should not
believe Gear Head when he says my new car design, the steam locomotive
converted to run on roller skates, is not practical. He's only saying
that because he is secretly jealous of my automotive design prowess!
64. We should invest
in hydrogen fuel cell technology. Gear Head has said that it is easily
possible to convert 90% of California's vehicles to run on fuel cell
technology within the next 10 years, so if we push the technology now,
we can significantly improve California's air quality within a few
years. (Check the information on Drive Train
before doing this one.)
Evaluation
An argument, any argument, only succeeds if the facts given
in its premises logically support its conclusion. If whatever facts
there are do not support the conclusion, the argument does not work, and
thus fails to prove its conclusion. In evaluating any argument, you
always ask yourself two basic questions. First, you ask yourself whether
or not all the premises of the argument are clearly true. Second, you
ask yourself whether or not those premises provide so much support for
the conclusion, that it would be unreasonable of you to continue to
believe that that conclusion is false. If there is a premise that does
not seem clearly seem to be true, then you would ask for and then
evaluate the arguments supporting that premise, which would bring you
back to thinking about whether those premises support that conclusion.
So in either case, you will find yourself thinking about whether or not
some set of facts supports some particular conclusion.
Facts
A fact is a claim to which all reasonable people will readily assent. It
is something already proven. It is uncontroversial. If a rational
audience cannot be expected to nod agreement when you say it, it's not a
fact. If it's something upon which reasonable people would disagree,
then it's just a claim. Claims can be well-considered judgments, casual
opinions or wild-eyed delusions. I'm only worried about facts, because
only facts can support conclusions. (For the purposes of this course
I'll just ask you to take my word for what are facts and what are
claims. In fact, I'm going to need you to take anything I treat as a
fact to actually be a fact, at least for purposes of discussion. And at
the end of the course, if you've paid attention, and done your work, and
brushed your teeth, you'll be much better able to tell a fact from a
non-fact, won't you?)
A set of facts supports a conclusion if there's no reasonable way to
rationally explain those facts without assuming that the conclusion is
true. Another way to look at this is to ask whether some logical
principle connects the facts to the conclusion. If we can reasonably
explain those facts without assuming that the conclusion is true, or if
there is no real logical principle connecting the facts to the
conclusion, the argument is no good.
In general, the trick to evaluating arguments is to ask yourself whether
we can reasonably explain the facts given in the premises without also
assuming that the conclusion is true. If we can reasonably explain those
facts under a scenario that allows the conclusion to be false, then the
argument is no good. That is, if it is reasonably possible for all of
the facts to be true while the conclusion is false, the argument bites
the big one .... I mean it dies. This is because the truth of the facts
given in the premises doesn't compel us to believe in the truth of the
conclusion, and arguments only work when the facts in the premises give
us no alternative but to believe the conclusion.
For your in-class exercises, and in real life, you will need to be able
to explain exactly what is wrong with some bad argument. There are
various ways this can be done, depending on the type of error committed.
You might find it works best to point out some crucial fact that the bad
arguer has ignored. Or you might point out some genuine logical rule
that allows us to discount something that the bad arguer is offering as
evidence. Or maybe the best way will be to give the candidate principle
that the bad arguer is relying on, and explain why it is a bad candidate
principle.
Bad arguments can have true conclusions, but we can't ever be sure that
something is true unless there's a logically compelling argument for it.
You can believe whatever you like, but if you can't back it up with a
logically compelling argument, you can't ever say that other people should
believe it.
Fact Mining
A good first step in evaluating any argument is to separate out the
facts given in the argument from the arguer's opinions. An arguer can
only expect us to take something as a fact if it is a claim that
everyone agrees on, or is at least a claim that is much less
controversial than the conclusion of her argument. Arguers often try to
sneak their own opinions into the premises of their arguments in order
to make their arguments appear stronger than they are. Don't be fooled.
Take something as a fact only if it is reasonably uncontroversial. The
things that an arguer ultimately wants you to believe are always his
opinions. They can never be taken as facts.
In the "Uncle Jeff" example, the facts and opinions break down as
follows.
Fact. Uncle Jeff says that Lutherans worship Lex Luthor.
Fact. Uncle Jeff is a Presbyterian minister.
I call these claims facts because they seem relatively uncontroversial
to me. Nobody is disputing these claims, and I see no particular reason
to disagree with either of them. Now he is the claim that I consider to
be an opinion.
Opinion. Lutherans worship Lex Luthor.
I call this an opinion because it is controversial. It is something the
arguer believes, and wants us to believe, but it is also something that
we are unlikely to believe unless we are given very good reason. Since
we had not yet decided whether the Uncle Jeff argument gives us a good
reason to believe it, we can’t say that we have good reason right now,
and so we should call it an opinion at this point.
Exercise 2.11. For each of the following arguments,
write down a list of facts and a list of opinions. If you find you have
to fill in something that isn't explicitly stated, put it in
parenthesis, like a suppressed premise. (I'm going to put in at least
one opinion for each question. This will usually be the person's
conclusion.)
95.
Nikki: Dinosaurs were around when humans first walked the
earth. That's what my grandpa says, and he should know
because he's really old.
96.
Anyaial: Dude! Your grandpa was joking when he said that!
97.
Easton: I just had my first cat juggling lesson. Boy, those
cats were mad when we juggled them! They seemed okay
afterwards though.
98.
Daquan: How can you say cat juggling is okay?
Everyone I know says that juggling is the worst thing you can do to a cat!
99.
Salvatore: Flush Limburger says that adultery is worse than
distorting evidence to justify an invasion in which lots of people die.
100.
Asher: Yeah baby, but Flush Limburger is a plumber,
baby!
101.
Simone: No-one has ever seen even the slightest piece of
evidence for the existence of Dragons.
102.
Kyleigh: Dragons are real. You can trust me on this
one.
103.
Stacy: Monkey's don't got wings, no animal flies
without wings, so monkeys don't fly.
104.
Kane: Yeah, well, a bum on the street told me that
monkeys really can fly, so we should all wear hats.
105.
Jaron: The state department recently announced that Saddam
Hussein was a transvestite.
106.
Nicolette: Yeah, but they just did it because they
were really, really bored that day.
107.
Mollie: The Hitlerage Institute has announced that critical
thinking will inevitably destroy society as we know it.
108.
Gunnar: The Hitlerage Institute is an advertising
industry research group. What do they know about thinking?
The one way of distinguishing facts from opinions that you're not
allowed to do is to pick the side of an argument that you like and say
that it has "facts" while the other side only has "opinions." To make up
your mind this way is biased, and simply demonstrates prejudice on your
part, so don't do it.
An argument only succeeds if it is clear to you, as a reasonable person,
that it presents a clear and compelling logical reason for you to change
your mind and agree with the conclusion. If it doesn't seem clear to you
that the argument has presented such a reason, then the argument has
failed, even if you passionately agree with its conclusion.
The Bottom Line
The basic trick to evaluating an argument from authority is to ask
whether the information we have available supports the idea that the
quoted source is an independent and reliable source of information on
this topic. If we had any information that suggests that the quoted
source is not independent and reliable, we should ignore the source. If
someone tries to undermine the source by giving us information (or
fantasy) that has nothing to do with the source's independence or
reliability, then we should ignore that irrelevant information.
The problem with arguments from authority is that, even in the best of
them, we still rely on someone's word. logically compelling arguments
from authority get their strength from the fact that we can generally
rely on the word of people who have already done the critical thinking
necessary to determine the truth of the matter. Still, they don't give
us any reason that we can examine to see for ourselves if their judgment
is good or bad. Thus they are a fairly weak form of argument, only to be
relied on when there is nothing else in play.
Exercises
In real life a critical thinker who is working on a particular issue
will look around for whatever arguments might be relevant to that issue,
and will consider any arguments that are offered regarding that issue,
whether he thinks they will turn out to be relevant or not. In this
class we won't bother with that. Instead we will consider small sets of
opposing arguments and pretend that each small set comprises all the
arguments available. This makes it easier to focus on specific logical
principles.
I like to base my examples and exercises on dialogs in which two
speakers argue against each other. While there is no such thing as a
completely ironclad argument, some arguments are clearly much weaker
than others, and I will try to provide you with exercises and exam
questions in which one argument is clearly weaker than the other. For
teaching purposes, I require you to trust the "speakers" in each dialog
as far as facts are concerned, but to be very suspicious where
judgments, or inferences from facts are concerned. This is because we
are here concerned with distinguishing between legitimate and
illegitimate rules of inference, and we need to treat some claims as
facts in order to decide what can and cannot be inferred from those
"facts." This means that when you are evaluating arguments in my
dialogs, you must assume that all the factual claims in the dialog are
true. Even if you disagree with some factual claim made by some arguer,
you are generally supposed to assume that that claim is true for the
purpose of evaluating the arguments in that dialog. (This will get a bit
more complicated later, but I will explain the complications as they
come up.)
If you want to do well in this class, you should do all of the exercises
provided for practice. This is because critical thinking is primarily an
attitude or mindset and only secondarily a set of concepts and
techniques. The critical thinking attitude is characterized by a
determination to think for oneself, and unwillingness to take anybody
else's word for anything, and a determination to settle issues on the
basis of logic rather than emotion. A person who knows all the concepts
and techniques but who doesn't have the critical thinking attitude will
totally fail to be a critical thinker, whereas someone who has the
mindset will (eventually) succeed as a critical thinker, even if she
doesn't start out knowing any of the concepts or techniques. The only
real way to build up a mindset is to inhabit it on a daily basis, and
the only way to do that is to do as many of these exercises as you can.
The first five exercises involve an imaginary radio personality, Dr.
Laura Schlockslinger, (loosely based on someone else), but they are not
based on anything particular that any real person has said. Just pretend
that she said the words I put into her mouth here for the purposes of
these exercises, and remember that I am no authority on what the real
Dr. Laura has or hasn't said. (And I may be prejudiced!) For your
information, both the real and the imaginary Dr. Laura holds a doctoral
degree in physiology. Neither has any training or experience in
philosophy, theology or moral reasoning. Got that? No training in
philosophy, theology or moral reasoning! The books and radio shows of
both are filled with claims about morality. For purposes of this
exercise, I am going to say that our Dr. Laura doesn't like Larry Flynt.
(My only evidence for this is just the fact that the real one once tried
to organize a boycott of a surf shop that sold a surfing magazine
published by Flynt.)
Your mission is to evaluate all of the arguments found in each of the
following dialogs. You don't have to commit yourself to saying that one
argument is absolutely perfect and the other is absolutely terrible. You
do have to say which side has the stronger argument(s) and which is
weaker. It might be helpful to remember that the basic way to evaluate
any argument is to figure out what candidate principle is being offered
to relate the available facts to the conclusion, and figuring out if
that candidate principle is logically valid. The "right way rule" might
also be helpful. You can standardize, context and/or analyze the
argument sets on paper if it helps you. You can even do a full fist of
death if that's helpful. But you don't have to do those things if you
can figure out which argument is better and which is worse. Determining
who commits a fallacy and who doesn't is also helpful. Exam questions
may well ask you to identify various fallacies. Oh, and make sure you
take the above background information on Dr. Laura Schlockslinger into
account as you evaluate the Schlockslinger arguments. (Just in case you
forgot, in the example of phony refutation given way up above above it
is NELL who commits the fallacy. Vicky commits no fallacy!)
Exercises
2.12. Tyshawn.
I think that sex education is a good idea. It would help kids cope
with their sexual feelings if they knew where they were coming from
and what they could lead to.
Magdalena. You'd think that
wouldn't you. The problem is, Dr. Laura Schlockslinger says that sex
education is immoral and dangerous, so we should ban it from schools.
That proves that sex education is a bad idea.
Tyshawn. Isn't Schlockslinger a
Ph.D. in physiology? What does that have to do with morality?
Magdalena. Don't change the
subject! She's a doctor, isn't she? That should be enough for you.
2.13. Sonny.
Although I personally find Larry Flynt to be a disgusting person, I've
got to admire the way he's dealt with being paralyzed. All those new
magazines and other businesses he's started show he hasn't let being
in a wheelchair slow him down.
Mireya. Dr. Laura Schlockslinger
says that Larry Flynt is faking the injuries that put him in a
wheelchair, so he's a fraud!
2.14. Tatiana.
Dr. Laura Schlockslinger claims that human cloning will cause nothing
but misery for everyone concerned. She says that the clones will grow
up desperately unhappy, their parents will be unhappy, and the
practitioners of cloning will be especially unhappy when they see all
the misery they have caused.
Darrion. But Dr. Laura has made
many pronouncements like that over the years, and almost none of her
dire predictions have come true, so I don't really think that we can
take her word for the future of human cloning.
2.15. Milton.
Dr. Laura Schlockslinger has collected a wide variety of scientific
papers saying that human cloning involves all sorts of physiological
problems that are not well reported in the media, and that these
problems could have devastating consequences for any human clone, so
she says that uncontrolled human cloning carries horrendous moral
risks.
Julien. But that's false
authority because Dr. Laura is always saying that this thing or that
thing carries moral risks! Just turn on her radio show, or open one of
her books! You will find her saying that some thing is morally wrong.
She's always saying that something is morally wrong, and she never
says that anything is morally okay, so if she talks about something,
she's obviously going to say that that thing is morally wrong. So
obviously, we can ignore her claim that human cloning has moral risks.
2.16. Kacie.
Dr. Laura Schlockslinger says that people learn quickest when their
work is competently criticized, and that therefore teachers should not
be banned from criticizing students' work.
Rylie. But that just proves
that teachers should be banned from criticizing students' work! You
know how conservative Dr. Laura is, and how little she really knows
about education, so obviously criticism is bad educational practice.
2.17. Solomon.
Did you hear that Doctor Beauregard Vineyard has proved that all the
mountains in the world are in fact artificial structures erected in
the distant past by super intelligent cows from other planets?
Deborah. Um, how do you know he's
proved this?
Solomon. Because he says so in
his new book, All of Our Mountains Were Erected by Cows. And he is the
world's leading authority on ancient bovine astronauts. You know this
because he was prominently featured in the world-famous documentary
"What the Moo Do We Know?"
Deborah. But can we trust a
movie?
Solomon. Normally, no. But we
know this movie is accurate because it was lavishly praised on the
website www.astrocowmountainmakers.com.
Deborah. Is this website on the
level?
Solomon. Of course it is! Dr.
Beauregard Vineyard says that this website is the most accurate and
up-to-date source of information on ancient bovine astronauts and
their mountain-making activities in the history of the world.
Deborah. Uh-huh.
2.18. Alfonso.
You really should take the ancient bovine mountain builders seriously.
Dr. Beauregard Vineyard insists that they existed, and he is in fact
the world's only authority on the subject. In fact, he has done an
enormous amount of research on the subject, and is written nearly 300
books documenting all the evidence on this issue.
Joey. Doesn't he make his
living writing these books? How much money would he make if he came
out and said that these ancient bovine astronauts didn't exist after
all?
Alfonso. Well, if he didn't say
they existed, his books wouldn't sell, he would have to find another
way to make a living.
Joey. Exactly!
2.19. Macie.
You like action figures. Why don't you go out and buy a full set of
the "Ancient Bovine Astronauts" figures, now on sale everywhere.
Amari. You think I should buy a
bunch of figures of cows in space suits with shovels and dump trucks
full of schist?
Macie. Dr. Beauregard Vineyard
says they're the most authentic Ancient Bovine Astronaut figures there
ever could be.
Amari. Doesn't he also own the
company that makes these action figures?
Macie. Yeah, so?
2.20. Kenya.
Dr. Rama Pithicus tells us that modern humans emerged from their
pre-human ancestors in the vicinity of Bakersfield over 2 million
years ago, so Dr. Crow Magnum could not have been using appropriate
archaeological techniques when he decided that modern humans
originated in Melbourne Australia, 2 million years ago.
Malia. But Dr. Crow Magnum is
every bit as qualified as Dr. Rama Pithicus, so it must be Pithicus
who wasn't using appropriate techniques.
2.21. Ramiro.
Professor Her She has been studying chocolate for over 40 years. His
study of chocolate took place at the top chocolate research
labortories and universities in the world, and he has been repeatedly
certified as the expert on the composition and effects of chocolate in
the entire world. So when he says that liberal applications of
chocolate on the scalp can cure baldness, you had better believe him,
especially since he has absolutely no financial interest in this
issue.
Angie. Doesn't Professor Her
She have a long history of making outrageous claims about chocolate,
all of which have turned out to be false?
Ramiro. Yes, but that doesn't
matter, because he is still the world's foremost authority on
chocolate.
2.22. Deshawn.
Did you know that the Humanity Research Council has condemned the
showing of nature films in hotel rooms. They say that these films
promote domestic violence by encouraging men to act like male lions
and tigers around the house, stalking their innocent family members
before pouncing upon them and biting them savagely about the neck and
shoulders. We must join the effort to prevent hotels from making
nature films available to their guests.
Aurora. What kind of track
record does the Humanity Research Council have for its pronouncements
about things that influence people to act like animals?
Deshawn. Well, I don't know about
their track record, but they are well known, and well-established
advocacy group.
L. Alessandro. I was just reading a report by
some feminist group or other. They took World Health Organization and
United Nations statistics for the amount of the world's work that is
done by women and compared it to the amount of the world's wealth that
is actually controlled by women. It turns out that two-thirds of the
world's work is actually done by women while only five percent of the
world's wealth is controlled by women.
Liliana. That is complete and utter nonsense! Don't you know
that PARADE magazine reported that 86 percent of all the personal
wealth in the United States is owned by women! 86 percent! Now do you
see that those feminists don't know what they're talking about?
M. Edith.
Did you know that Pickup Styx, the chief Uninvited Napkins cuisine
inspector, still maintains that there were no significant stocks of
waffles of messy dessert items in Pastria at the time of the Cordon
Bleu invasion of that country.
Carina. Are you nuts? Absolutely everyone I know says
that Pastria had massive stocks of those messy dessert waffles at the
time of the invasion! Everyone in my knitting circle has a different
story of some clever way those Pastry Cooks hid some kind of waffle,
and just about everyone in my book club has got a similar story. Who
does this Pickup Styx think he is, going up against all my friends and
acquaintances!
Possible Quiz Questions (By the time you finish this
chapter, you should easily be able to answer these questions. If you
can't, go back and read the relevant sections again.)
Should we trust an authority who has frequently been wrong about this
kind of issue?
Should we trust an authority whose only expertise is in a completely
unrelated field?
Should we trust an authority who stands to make a lot of money if you
believe him in this particular case?
Should we disregard an authority because of some fact about him that has
nothing to do with his use of his expertise?
Should we disregard an authority merely because she could have
a vicious motive or material interest for saying what she says?
Does the fact that an authority makes a claim ever, by itself,
prove that the authority has a vicious motive or material interest?
Should we trust an authority who relies on her feelings rather than her
expertise?
Should we believe a claim merely because everyone else, or nearly
everyone else believes it?
Should we disregard an authority merely because she has a track record
of saying nothing but bad things about a particular person?
Should we disregard an authority merely because someone else has loudly
disrespected her to us?
What's the difference between ad hominem and fallacy of slander?
What's the difference between fallacy of slander and poisoning the well?
What's the difference between ad hominem and phony refutation?
1. Regan. Don't you
know that Professor Bar Soom says that the Mars Meteorites constitute
definitive proof that there was once life on Mars.
Madisyn. But Bar Soom is a professor of literature
who studies Edgar Rice Burroughs' Mars novels!
2. Aden. I just read a fascinating book by man
called Harold Peterson, who spent ten years researching the history of
baseball. He says that baseball was brought to America by the British
in the 1750's under the name of "rounders." Modern baseball was
established and popularized in the 1840s and 50's by Alexander
Cartwright and his friends of the Knickerbocker Base Ball Club.
Lizette. That's ridiculous. Everyone knows Abner
Doubleday invented baseball at Cooperstown in 1839.
3. Beau. Man, liberalism must be a mental disease!
Those people have no sense of facts or logic
Issac. Actually, the liberals I talk to are very
well-informed, and they usually use good logic
Beau. Man, you've got to stop listening to them. It's
a mental disease I tell you!
4. Tracy. Colonel Whiz Bang, the military aviation
expert, is well-known for his knowledge of air fleet strengths. He
says that the U.S. Army actually has more aircraft than US Air Force!
Justus. Yeah, but Colonel Whiz Bang is a war
criminal! He bombed two hospitals, an orphanage and a petting zoo
during the Vietnam war.
Tracy. But does that affect his military aviation
expertise? And, anyway, he was probably trying to hit legitimate
military targets.
Justus. In Cincinnati? No man, the air force must
have way more aircraft!
5. Gunner. The well-known biblical scholar, Dr.
Harry Mathea, says that there is no evidence that the fruit of the
tree of the knowledge of good and evil in the garden of Eden was
actually an apple. In fact, he says it was more likely to have been a
fig.
Talon. Well that just proves that Harry Mathea has
money in the fig business! He must have bought shares in fig ranches,
and he's spreading this story to increase sales.
Exercise Answers
2.2. None of these arguments cites
any person or group as the source of its conclusion. Each one of them
bases its conclusion on some fact that has nothing to do with whatever
any person or group says.
2.3. 16. Authority. The only evidence is given in
support of the claim that horses can fly is that the USDA classifies
horses as flying mammals. As no
other evidence is given, the reliability of the USDA is the only support
the conclusion has, so this can only be an authority argument.
17. Not authority. The argument
gives instances where Saddam Hussein has cross-dressed. If they really
happened, that would be evidence
that Saddam was a transvestite. This is different from giving an
authority argument because it gives independent evidence for
the
conclusion rather than saying that somebody says that he's a
transvestite.
18. Authority. (Flush Limburger )
19. Not authority. The argument is
based on what is known about Canadian monkeys. Canadian monkeys are
presumed to be representative
of all monkeys. No source is given for the claim that all monkeys can
fly, so this is not an authority argument.
20. Authority. (The Republican
National Committee)
21. Authority. ( Oil industry
scientists )
22. Not authority. This argument is
based on claims about the existence of specific dragons at specific
places. If we know that specific,
identifiable dragons exist at specific locations, then it follows that
dragons really exist, and the argument is not based on any claim about
what any particular person says.
23. Authority. (Dogpatch ASU)
24. Authority. (Namor, Prince of
Atlantis, )
25. Not authority. No source is
given for the claim that juggling is bad for cats. Instead, a list of
alleged juggling-related injuries is given.
26. Authority. (The Pope )
27. Not authority. The argument
claims that critical thinking instruction is the same as the terrorist
training. The arguer seems to assume that
we will think that terrorist training is bad, and expects us to
conclude that the alleged similarity between the two things that will
lead us
to conclude that critical thinking instruction is bad also. The argument
relies on a similarity between two objects, and not on the word of
some authority, so it is not an authority argument.
28. Authority. (President Bush )
29. Not authority. The argument
gives physical evidence that can only be explained by assuming that a
dinosaur (the tyrannosaur) and a
human being (the guy with the eight track and Betamax) were alive at the
same time. This does not involve taking anybody's word for
anything, so this is not an authority argument.
30. Authority. (The entire Mormon
Tabernacle Choir )
2.4. 31. Yes. She has a good track record, and we have
no reason to think she's not using her expertise this time.
32. No. This person has a bad track
record.
33. No. Her judgment could be
consciously or unconsciously influenced by her particular interest.
34. No. His application of his
expertise might have been influenced by his interest.
35. No. Training in the wrong
subject is just as bad as no training at all.
36. No. A good track record in the
wrong subject is just as bad as a bad track record in this subject.
37. Yes. Most real-life cases in
which we accept someone as an authority fall into this situation.
38. Yes. Most real-life experts
make their livings as experts. If they don't make every effort to be
accurate, they won't be able to make money.
39. Yes. Her general interest
did not affect her judgment before, so we should not think that it is
affecting her judgment now.
40. No. We have no evidence that he
has ever been right, or that his reputation depends on a track record
for accuracy.
41. No. If the other authority has
a similar track record, then he is equally likely to be right.
42. No. When comparably qualified
experts disagree, they are both equally likely to be right..
2.5 43. Phony Refutation. (It looks like it
refutes the other argument, but in reality it ignores the other
argument.)
44. Special Pleading. (He wants us
to accept authority where it favors him, but reject
it when it opposes him.)
45. Fallacy of slander. (The arguer
makes an unfounded slander of bias.)
46. False Authority. (The authority
has a specific personal interest in this issue.)
47. Ad Hominem. (The arguer cites a
true but irrelevant fact about the person.)
48. False Authority. (The
“authority” is actually not an authority at all.)
49. Poisoning the Well. (Tries to
get you to discount an authority when his expertise is actually not in
question.)
50. False Authority. (If the field
is unrelated, he can’t have the right expertise.)
51. Ad Populum. (A million
non-experts is no better than a single non-expert.)
52. False Authority. (Bad track
record.)
53. Circular Argument. (If there’s
no independent evidence of expertise, then there’s no expertise,
period.)
54. Red Herring. (Anti authority
arguments only work on authority arguments.)
2.6. 55. Phony refutation. (The argument addresses
Chain Smoker’s behavior, not his expertise.)
56. Circular Argument. (These guys
all back each other up, but nothing else does.)
57. False Authority. (Nothing
overcomes a bad track record.)
58. Ad Populum. (It’s just
based on what people say.)
59. Poisoning the Well. (He does
nothing but disparage Gear Head.)
60. False Authority. (No known
qualifications nor track record. Just some random guy.)
61. Ad Hominem. (A felony
conviction has nothing to do with engineering.)
62. False Authority. (Eye Ball has
a financial interest here.)
63. Fallacy of slander. (Unfounded
slander of bias.)
64. Special Pleading. (Equally
qualified Drive Train disagrees, so the “trust authority” rule
goes both ways.)
2.11. For each of the following arguments, write down a
list of facts and a list of opinions. If you find you have to fill in
something that isn't explicitly stated, put it in parenthesis, like a
suppressed premise.
95. Fact. Nikki's
grandpa says that dinosaurs were around when humans first walked the
earth.
Fact. Nikki's grandpa is really old.
Opinion. Dinosaurs were around when humans first walked
the earth.
96. It's pretty
plausible to think that Nikki's grandpa really was joking, so I'll call
this a fact. If you called it an opinion, that's okay.
(Opinion. Dinosaurs were not around when humans first
walked the earth.)
97. Fact. Easton
just had his first cat juggling lesson.
Fact. The cats were angry when they were juggled.
Fact. The cats seemed okay after the juggling.
(Opinion. Cat juggling is not bad for cats.)
98. Fact.
Everyone Daquan knows says that juggling is the worst thing you can do
to a cat.
Opinion. Juggling is the worst thing you can do to a
cat.
99. Fact. Flush
Limburger says that adultery is worse than distorting evidence to
justify an invasion in which lots of people die.
Opinion. Adultery is worse than distorting evidence to
justify an invasion in which lots of people die.
100. Fact. Flush Limburger is
a plumber.
(Opinion. Flush Limburger is not an expert on
morality.)
101. Fact.
No-one has ever seen even the slightest piece of evidence for
the existence of Dragons.
(Opinion. There are no dragons.)
102. Fact. Kyleigh says that
dragons are real.
Opinion: Dragons are real.
103. Fact. Monkeys don't have
wings.
Fact. No animal flies without wings.
Opinion. Monkeys don't fly.
104. Fact. A bum on the
street told Kane that monkeys really can fly.
Opinion. Monkeys can fly.
105. Fact. The state
department announced that Saddam Hussein was a transvestite.
Opinion. Saddam Hussein was a transvestite.
106. Fact. The state
department was really, really bored that day.
(Opinion. Saddam Hussein was not a transvestite.)
107. Fact. The Hitlerage
Institute says that critical thinking will destroy society as we know
it.
Opinion. Critical thinking will destroy society as we
know it.
108. Fact. The Hitlerage
Institute is an advertising industry research group.
Opinion. The Hitlerage Institute is not an expert on
critical thinking.
For the last few exercises, the information that is really necessary for
a critique will be in bold type.
2.12. Based on the dialog between Tyshawn and
Magdalena, sex education is a good idea. As Tyshawn says, sex eduction
would help kids cope with their sexual feelings. It is a
well-established fact that becoming properly informed about a type of
situation is usually enormously useful, and being uninformed is usually
extremely dangerous, and can be fatal, depending on the type of
situation. I know of no situations in which people do better when they
know less about what's going on. Because this fact is so well
established, Magdalena, who thinks sex education should be
banned, has to come up with an extremely compelling reason if she is
to prove her point. Magdalena points out that the imaginary authority,
Dr. Laura Schlockslinger, has stated that sex education is immoral and
dangerous. If Dr. Schlockslinger is right, that would give us ample
reason to ban sex education from schools. Unfortunately for Magdalena,
Dr. Laura Schlockslinger is not an expert in either sex education or
morality. She's a physiologist, which gives her no expertise in this
particular area, and thus we can, and should, discount her statements.
Without a qualified authority to back her up, Magdalena's argument
fails.
2.13. Based on facts supplied by Sonny and Mireya,
Larry Flynt is admirable. Sonny cites Larry Flynt's achievements to show
that there is something admirable about Flynt, and it's very reasonable
to admire someone who achieves a lot while wheelchair bound. However, Mireya
cites Schlockslinger's authority as a physiologist to show that Flynt
is a fraud. Sonny's argument depends on Flynt actually being
wheelchair-bound. Starting new magazines and other businesses is not
really that admirable if one is not confined to a wheelchair. Dr.
Schlockslinger is a Ph.D. in physiology, which would qualify to
discuss people's injuries and disabilities, but she has a well know
animus against Flynt. That's not a material interest exactly, but she
does have a track record of saying unfounded bad things about Flynt,
so if she said this we'd have to discount it until we had evidence
from an independent physiologist who could care less about Larry
Flynt's life and work.
2.14. Based on the above dialog between Tatiana and
Darrion, human cloning will not cause widespread misery. If
Tatiana thinks that somebody else's actions will cause harm, it's up
to Tatiana to come up with the evidence that it will cause harm. If
this wasn't the rule, we would have to prove every new thing harmless
before we could do it. Tatiana cites Dr. Schlockslinger as an
authority for her claim that human cloning will be harmful. But it's
hard to see how Schlockslinger could be qualified here and, as Darrion
points out, she has a terrible track record, so double nuts to
Tatiana. Even if Schlockslinger had substantial expertise in this
matter, her unsupported word would not be enough to support this claim
because we have evidence that she isn't good at making such
predictions. Based on this, clones won't be miserable.
2.15. The preponderance of evidence given here by
Milton and Julien supports the idea that human cloning does indeed carry
moral risks. Dr. Laura seems qualified here because she's collected the
relevant scientific papers, which is what experts are supposed to do.
Milton appears to be giving an authority argument because he cites
Schlockslinger, but notice that he actually refers to a wide variety of
scientific papers, all of which Schlockslinger is competent to analyze
because of her doctorate in physiology. Schlockslinger's Ph.D. at least
qualifies her to find and read scientific papers, and she has no bias
here, so we have no reason to discount her claims in this case. Julien
attacks Milton's argument by accusing Milton of commiting the fallacy
of false authority. He supports this by pointing out that
Schlockslinger has a long track record of making precisely this kind
of claim. Julien accuses Milton of relying on a biased authority, but
his evidence for that bias is merely that Schlessinger predominately
comments on things she thinks are morally wrong. Since the fact that
someone makes it her business to point out bad stuff doesn't by itself
mean that she's wrong about anything, Julien is bringing up a point
that has nothing to do with the issue.
2.16. Based on Kacie's and Rylie's arguments, teachers
should be allowed to criticize student's work. This is actually a very
well established educational principle, and so we already have very good
reason to believe it. We should only disbelieve it if someone comes up
with an extremely compelling argument against it. This Rylie totally
fails to do. Rylie argues that teachers should not be allowed
to criticize student work because Schlockslinger says they should, and
she's an idiot. But no matter how stupid Schlockslinger is, her
stupidity can't change any facts, so she can't make something false
merely by saying it's true. Schlockslinger isn't the only person in
favor of criticism, so Rylie's got to come up with something that
covers everyone who supports the idea of criticizing students's work.
Unfortunately, his premise only applies to Schlockslinger! Since the
usefulness of criticism is already accepted by educational
professionals, it doesn't really need Dr. Laura's support, so
since Rylie failed to meet his burden of proof, and the most rational
conclusion here is that criticism is good educational practice.
2.17. Based on the dialog between Solomon and Deborah,
we should say that proposition that all of our mountains were erected by
cows is absolutely false. Our present understanding of
mountains and cows implies that Dr. Vineyard's thesis could not
possibly be true. If Dr. Vineyard was a competent authority, this
might give us some reason to believe his thesis. However, his claim to
expertise is based on a documentary movie, whose only claim to
authenticity is in turn backed up by a website, that is itself only
certified as an authority by Dr. Vineyard himself. This is a
completely circular argument that provides absolutely no independent
support for Dr. Vineyard's claim to expertise. Thus, Solomon's
argument commits the fallacy of false authority.
2.18. The dialogue between Alfonso and Joey does not,
by itself, really give us enough information to settle this issue. Our
pre-existing knowledge of plate tectonics and cow history so strongly
contradicts Dr. Vineyard's thesis that we would need absolutely
incontrovertible evidence that it was true before we would even begin
to think about the possibility of even thinking that it might be true,
and in the word of a single expert, even if impeccably qualified would
simply not be enough. Alfonso does cite the only person who could
possibly be an authority on this subject but, since he does not cite a
track record or any other evidence that Dr. Vineyard has done actual
critical thinking about this issue, we don't really even have the
beginnings of an authority argument. On the other hand, Joey's
argument is no good either. The fact that Dr. Vineyard makes his
living by writing about this theory does not mean that he's not an
authority, simply because the majority of reputable experts make their
livings by writing about their subjects.
2.19. The dialog between Macie and Amari suggests that
we have no real reason to think that the "Ancient Bovine Astronauts"
figures are the most authentic Ancient Bovine Astronaut figures there
ever could be. Macie relies upon the authority of Dr.
Beauregard Vineyard who, as the world expert on the Ancient Bovine
Astronauts theory would normally be considered the premier expert on
the authenticity of Ancient Bovine Astronaut figures, but he happens
to own the company that makes this particular figures, and so he has a
strong financial interest in this issue. Given this interest, we
cannot take his word on this issue, and Macie commits the fallacy of
false authority by relying on his word.
2.20. The dialogue between Kenya and Malia gives us no
basis for saying anything about the origin of modern humans. Both
speakers accuse the other of citing an authority who misuses his
expertise, but the only evidence they give is that the other expert
disagrees. Although disagreement between experts suggests that someone
has messed up, the mere fact of disagreement does not tell us which
one of them it was. However, because equally qualified experts
disagree about this issue, we simply cannot rely on authority to
settle the question. Furthermore, because each speaker wants us to
accept his favored authority while at the same time rejecting another,
equally qualified authority, they both commit the fallacy of special
pleading.
2.21. After considering the dialogue between Ramiro and
Angie, we have no real reason to think that rubbing chocolate on one's
head can cure baldness. It is true that professor Her She has
an enormous amount of expertise and no financial interest in the
matter, but he also has a history of making outrageous statements that
turn out not to be true. That, by itself, is enough to disqualify him
as an authority, and so Ramiro commits the fallacy of false authority
by citing an authority with a bad track record.
2.22. Based on the information in the conversation
between Deshawn and Aurora, we should not try to make hotels stop
showing nature films to their guests. Everything should be
considered morally okay unless we have a specific reason to think that
it is morally bad, so Deshawn bears the burden of proving that it is
morally wrong for hotels to make nature films available to their
guests. He tries to do this by citing the Humanity Research Council, a
well known advocacy group. However, being a well-known advocacy group
does not establish a good car track record or any other kind of
qualification. Since the Humanity Research Council has no actual
qualifications, it really cannot count as an authority, and Deshawn
commits false authority.