Chapter Six.                                                                        (Problems printing? Click here.)
Next page.


Reversed causality. Gotta imprision peaceful protestors, because disagreement with government can escalate to violent opposition.



Causal Arguments

"Causal" reasoning is reasoning about cause-and-effect relationships. Causal arguments do not support claims about the existence or non-existance of objects, nor about the occurance or non-occurance of events. They just support claims about causal relationships. Thus no causal argument would support a claim that tile roofs exist, nor would any causal argument support a claim that baldness happens. But if someone wanted to support a claim that tile roofs cause baldness, well, then, that claim would have to be backed up by a causal argument. (Notice that a causal claim is just a claim that A causes B. It is not a claim that anyone knows how A causes B.)

Causality is basically a relationship between one object or event and another object or event. If we were to say that A causes B, we would mean that there is a relationship between A and B such that whenever A occurs, we should expect B to occur also. Causal claims are therefore conditional predictions. They are predictions about what will happen next IF something else has just happened. Causal arguments are therefore attempts to get people to believe in these predictions. Causal arguments cannot prove that anything other than a relationship exists. No causal argument can prove that A exists or that B exists. For this reason, causal arguments can only establish relationships between known entities. If we don't already know that A exists and that B exists, we cannot make a causal argument about A and B. (We will cover arguments that prove things exist in the next chapter.)

Causal claims can only be justified on the basis of established correlations. It is often said that "correlation does not prove causation." This is completely and utterly false. Correlation is the only thing that ever proves causation. It's true that not every correlation proves causation, but every causal relationship that has ever been proved, has been proved on the basis of a correlation. (Thus the claim that "correlation does not prove causation" is logically analogous to the claim that "evidence does not prove guilt" in a court of law.) The trick here is to figure out which correlations prove causation, and which don't.

Causal relationships are usually not one-to-one relationships. Causes can have multiple effects, and effects can have multiple causes. Cigarette smoking does not cause cancer, emphysema or heart attack in everyone who smokes cigarettes. But we can bet that a group of a thousand people who smoke heavily we will see more cases of cancer, emphysema and heart attack than in a demographically identical group of a thousand nonsmokers. And ciggies are not the only things that cause cancer, emphysema and heart attack. So a cause is something that makes the effect more likely to happen but usually does not guarantee that the effect will happen.

It is important to remember that causal arguments do not have to come with explanations. When smoking was established as a cause of cancer, nobody had any idea how smoking managed to cause cancer. Nevertheless, the strong correlation between smoking cigarettes and getting cancer convinced reasonable people that a causal link existed. It didn't matter that nobody had any idea how smoking did it, all that mattered was that the correlation between cigarettes and cancer was so strong that no other explanation made sense. All that is necessary to establish a causal link is that a strong correlation be established. Explanations are immaterial to this correlation, so the lack of an explanation is never a weakness in a causal argument.

The way to evaluate a causal argument is to ask whether the known correlation is strong enough to justify the causal claim and, if it is, to then ask if all other causal possibilities have been eliminated. If it is, and they have, then your argument is good. If it isn't, or they haven't, then the argument sucks. While an argument that tile roofs cause baldness would have to start with some correlation between tile roofs and baldness, it wouldn't get very far unless it included reasons to eliminate all other possible causes of baldness, like, for instance, salsa music. (We wouldn't have to eliminate UFOs however. The fact that something has never been proved to exist is generally enough to remove it from consideration when we're talking causes.)

If somebody were to say that we should abolish tile roofs because they cause baldness we would evaluate his "causal claim" by asking him to give evidence of a correlation between baldness and tile roofs. If it turned out that men started losing their hair the moment they went under a tile roof, and that men who never lived under tile roofs never went bald, then we would have a strong correlation, and good reason to think that tile roofs cause baldness. If it turned out that men went bald or not independently of whether or not they lived under a tile roof, then we would have no correlation, and no reason to think that tile roofs cause baldness. So a causal argument that comes without at least some evidence of a correlation is always a bad argument.

First, some terminology. A positive correlation is when two things tend to happen together. Tile roofs and baldness are positively correlated if it is the case that tile roofs tend to show up every time baldness occurs, and vice versa.

A negative correlation is a correlation between non-occurrences. It's when two things tend to be absent at the same time. Tile roofs and baldness are negatively correlated if it is the case that tile roofs tend to be absent every time baldness is also absent, and vice versa.

John Stuart Mill figured out five different ways to support a causal connection, depending on what kind of evidence you have. (These methods may turn out to be "just common sense." I've noticed that students often have a hard time understanding explanations of Mill's methods. However, when I give those students exercises designed to test their ability to apply Mill's methods, they find those exercises ludicrously easy. This suggests that what I grandly describe as "Mill's Methods" can be figured out by community college students with no previous training in those methods. So, if you don't understand these explanations, don't worry about it. You will probably be able to do the exercises anyway.

Mill's method of agreement relies on positive correlations. It basically says rule out everything that is not necessary to bring about the effect, and what is left over is more likely to be the cause. Say we have a population of one thousand bald men and the only thing all of them have in common is that each of them spends long periods of time under a tile roof. If this were true, then anything else that was offered as a candidate for the cause could be eliminated by pointing out that somebody got bald without being exposed to that thing. Since tile roof is the only thing that cannot be so eliminated, we have good reason to think that tile roof is the cause.

Mill's method of difference says rule out everything that is not sufficient to bring about the effect. Say we have a population of one thousand hairy men and one bald man who lives apart from them under a tile roof. The only thing the hairy men all have in common is that none of them lives under a tile roof. In this case any other causal candidate could be eliminated by pointing out that somebody was exposed to that thing without getting bald. Since tile roof is the only thing that cannot be ruled out that way, we have good reason to think the tile roof is the cause of the baldness.

Mill's "joint method" just means applying both methods together to the same data set. If two things are both positively and negatively correlated, then that could be strong evidence that one of them causes the other.

Mill method of concomitant variation says look for something that varies in proportion to the effect. Say that Al has lived under tile for 7 years and is 10% bald, Ben has lived under tile for 14 years and is 20% bald, Cal lived under tile for 21 years and is 30% bald, Don has lived under tile 28 years for 40% baldness, Ed has 35 years and 50%, Finn 42 years and 60%, Greg 49 years and 70%, Hal 56 years and 80%, Ian 63 years and 90% while Jack has spent seventy years living under a tile roof and is completely bald. Since the amount of baldness goes up and down with the time of residence under tile, and if nothing else correlates in this way, this would give us good reason to think that living under a tile roof causes baldness. Remember that the corespondance doesn't have to be one to one. It can be any ratio at all, just as long as that ratio is constant across instances.

Mill's method of residuals is a way of figuring out how much of some effect can be attributed to some particular cause. Say that we know that polka music causes baldness in 4 percent of listeners, plaid shirts cause baldness in 8 percent of wearers, and that jumping jacks cause baldness in 16 percent of jumpers. And say that we know that these are the only causes of baldness apart from tile roofs. Finally say that we know that yesterday one million men wore plaid shirts to do jumping jacks to polka music under a tile roof, and 40 percent of them became bald. Ignoring the tile, we can account for no more than 32 percent of these baldnesses, (4+8+16=28), so being under a tile roof must cause baldness in at least 12 percent (40-28=12) of men.

You could apply Mill's methods to the following problems. You could, but I don't want you to. (At least, not yet.) Instead, I want you to evaluate the arguments that follow the problems. See if you think the person making a causal argument in each dialog is correctly applying Mill's methods.

Several patients at Chicago Soap Hospital are experiencing bizarre drug side effects. The hospital administrator, Dr. Whatmeworry, is going crazy, and has hired several people to figure out what is going on. Unfortunately, none of them seem to know what they're doing. Your job is to sort through the arguments and figure out who, if anyone, knows what he's talking about.

Some patients in Ward 1 are turning into fairies and have turned several doctors into animals. The patients who are growing gossamer wings and buying pixie hats are on Unicorp, Verlag, Xindeco and Zydigm. Those who are merely looking on in horror are on Verlag, Zydigm and Unicorp.

The patients in Ward 2 have all acquired the ability to shoot low energy laser beams from their eyeballs, which they use to irritate their nurses, warm beverages and vaporize insects. Patient Abel is on Terraplex, Omniken, Shegos and Permax. Patient Baker is on Omniken, Shegos and Terraplex. Patient Cooper is on Terraplex, Shegos and Permax. Patient Dasia is on Shegos, Omniken and Permax.

Ward 3 Patients are channeling famous generals of the past. They are now in great demand by TV networks as commentators on various wars. The camera crews are disrupting hospital operations, and one patient is faking symptoms (pretending to channel Buffy the Vampire Slayer) in order to get on The McLaughlin Group. Patient Killian is channeling Caesar and Napoleon. She is on Invap 40mg, Kolvox 100mg, Minafax 300mg, and Nasdaq 1mg. Patient Lomax is channeling Rommel, Wellington, Alexander and Sun-Tzu and she is on Invap 10mg, Kolvox 200mg, Minafax 600mg and Nasdaq 2mg. Patient Miles is just channeling Vinegar Joe Stilwell and she is on Invap 30mg, Kolvox 50mg, Minafax 900mg and Nasdaq 1mg. Finally, Patient North is channeling Grant, Zhukov and Sharon. She is on Invap 20mg, Kolvox 150mg, Minafax 600mg and Nasdaq 4mg.

Some patients in Ward 4 are growing extra limbs, which are presenting interesting possibilities for getting around the ward and possible future sporting events. Patient Eggar is growing an extra left foot from his right elbow, and is on Quindor, Dynastar, Comdex and Gennum. Patient Harris has no extra limbs, and is on Dynastar, Fitel and Gennum. Patient Frank amuses children with the extra arm growing out of his left kneecap, and is on Comdex, Dynastar, Fitel, Quindor, and Gennum. Patient Irvin is perfectly normal and on Fitel, Gennum and Comdex. Patient Gregg makes interesting gestures with the extra hand that has grown out of where his nose used to be. He is on Quindor, Comdex, Fitel and Dynastar. Patient Jakes wants an extra limb but, alas, has not developed one. He is on Fitel, Gennum, Dynastar and Comdex.


Here are the arguments I want you to evaluate.

Daryl. Don't take Zydigm! All of the people who turned into fairies took Zydigm, so it must be the cause!
Gwendolyn. Not everybody who took Zydigm turned into a fairy, so it's probably not the cause.

Aliya. The drug that gives people the ability to shoot laser beams from their eyes must be Terraplex. Able, Baker and Cooper all took Terraplex, and they all got laser vision.
Karson. Yeah, but Dasia got laser eyes too, and she didn't take Terraplex.

Gianni. The drug that lets you channel famous generals must be Nasdaq. Miles took 1 milligram of Nasdaq and channeled just one general, that's a 1-to-1 correlation, so Nasdaq must be the drug.
Susana. But Killian also took 1 milligram of Nasdaq, and she channeled 2 generals. Lomax took two milligrams, but she channeled four generals! Neither of those is a 1-to-1 correlation, so Nasdaq probably isn't the drug. And anyway, it doesn't have to be one unit of the drug to one general. We have to look for a situation where the number of generals goes up and down in exactly the same way that the dosage of the drug goes up and down.

Zoie. Dynastar must be the drug that is causing the extra limbs. Eggar, Frank and Gregg all took Dynastar and all grew extra limbs.
Tristian. But Harris and Jakes also took Dynastar, and neither of them grew any extra limbs.


Okay, now you can figure it out for yourself, if you want to. (I'm sure you can do a better job than these idiots.)


Arguing Against A Causal Claim

There are two basic ways to argue against a causal claim. I call these the "inconvenient fact method" and the "not so fast" method.

The inconvenient fact method is pretty simple. You'll notice in the dialogues above the person arguing against the first person's causal claim does so by bringing up some fact that cannot easily be explained on the assumption that the first person's causal claim is true. In the above dialogues, the second speaker gives us some reason to think that the first speaker has not applied Mill's methods correctly. The best causal argument will be the one that best fits the observed facts. If you can show that some causal claim does not fit the observed facts, you will have shown that the argument supporting that claim is not a good argument. The most inconvenient fact of all would of course be the fact that something else was just as strongly correlated with effect as the purported cause. If we have just as good evidence that something else causes the effect, then the evidence we have doesn't prove that our purported "cause" is the cause.

The not so fast method is applied to causal arguments that survive the inconvenient fact method. Such an argument presents us with an apparently good correlation. The not so fast method works by presenting an alternative explanation for that correlation. If that alternative explanation is at least roughly as good an explanation as the original causal claim, then the argument supporting that causal claim is no good. Consider the following.

Nasir. Okay, I understand that some people who took Zydigm didn't turn into fairies, but, it is a fact that all of the people who turned into fairies did take Zydigm. Nobody who didn't take Zydigm turned into a fairy, and Zydigm could be one of those causes that doesn't work every time. So I think that Zydigm probably is the drug that is causing people to turn into fairies.
Amya. Not so fast Jack! I mean Nasir. The same thing is true of Unicorp and Verlag. All of the people who turned into fairies took Unicorp and all of the people who turned into fairies took also Verlag. So the evidence is just as good for Unicorp and Verlag being the cause as it is for Zydigm being the cause of the fairification.


If Amya is right that Unicorp and Verlag are just as likely as Zydigm to be the cause, then Nasir's argument in favor of Zydigm is no good.


Evaluating Causal Arguments

To evaluate a causal argument you must figure out two things. First, you must figure out whether the causal claim offered is a good explanation for the observed correlation. Second, you must figure out whether or not there is any other reasonable explanation for that correlation. If it turns out that the offered causal claim really isn't a good explanation for all of the observed facts, then the argument is no good. If it turns out that some other explanation for the observed facts is just as good an explanation as the causal claim, then the argument is no good.

Since basically any bad causal argument can be called a "false cause" fallacy, I'm going to continue my discussion of bad causal arguments under that heading.

False Cause

The classic False Cause fallacy assumes a causal connection based on a trivial correlation. Anyone who makes a causal claim based on anecdotal evidence commits the fallacy of false cause.

Interviewer. "Coach, can you tell me why the fans are tossing cans of beans on to the field?
Coach. "Well, we haven't done well this season. We only beat Milwaukee, Dallas and Fargo. Just before that Milwaukee game I was embarrassed by a noisy attack of flatulence. Then, as I was psyching the team up for the Dallas game..."
Interviewer. "That was you? I thought it was a low-flying jet!"
Coach. "No that was me..."
Interviewer. "And the cheerleaders who fainted before the Fargo game?"
Coach. "Me again, I'm afraid."
Interviewer. "And so the beans..."
Coach. "If you'll excuse me, I think I can choke down another can.

I love your sister, but every time she comes to California we have an earthquake. So we can't invite her again until I've finished earthquake-proofing my collection of decorative plates.

Just because something is the only cause you can think of doesn't mean it has any causal relationship to the effect.

Pete: Since 1985, the average SAT scores of the incoming freshmen at Miskatonic University have consistently been about 10% better than they were before 1985. Nothing important changed in or around 1985. In fact, we've checked all the things that the schools could be doing that could possibly cause a rise in SAT scores, and we found that none of them changed significantly, so it isn't due to anything that local educators are doing.
Ona: Have you forgotten that I‘ve been teaching at Miskatonic since 1985. Obviously, that's the reason.
Pete: How do you figure that?
Ona: Well, duh, before I got here, the scores were bad. After I got here, the scores got better.


Sometimes people commit false cause when they get confused about causal relationships. People often assume that one thing causes (or must cause) another thing merely because the two things are strongly associated in their minds. But a mental association is a far cry from a causal relationship.

Why do we have drug laws? We have to have them because of all those drug-related murders! Those dealers will kill to keep their activities secret, you know!

Notice that the arguer here believes that laws against possession, use and sale of drugs actually reduce the murder rate. Also notice that the arguer does not offer any data whatsoever. Finally, notice that the arguer ignores a well-known causal relationship between criminalization of activities and murder. Students of history will recall that the criminalization of alcohol trafficking in the United States was followed by an enormous increase in the number of murders related to alcohol trafficking. This murder rate was drastically reduced by the later legalization of alcohol trafficking. Generally speaking, people do not kill to conceal activities that are not illegal.

People can commit false cause by completely reversing a causal relationship. That is to say, two things are correlated, but the wrong thing is identified as the cause.

Have you noticed how Jane gets depressed every time her cancer gets worse. If we could just cheer her up, that would take care of that nasty cancer!


Finally, it is sometimes the case that two things are correlated, not because one causes the other, but because some third factor causes both. This is called "ignoring a common cause."

Every time I put on a little weight, I lose a little hair. So if I exercise and go on a diet, I'll stop losing my hair.

Ignoring a common cause would be easier to understand if it was called "ignoring a possible common cause" because it is the fact that some third thing might be causing the correlation that makes the argument fail. Strictly speaking, all you have to to refute any causal argument and it is a very popular fallacy. It is often commited by people who want to believe that drug use, by itself, causes crime. If there is any reasonable possibility that a person's criminality and drug use have a common cause, such as poor upbringing or exposure to scofflaw culture, such as could reasonably be thought to have caused criminalty without exposure to drugs, then the correlation between drug use and criminality cannot prove that the drug use caused the criminal tendencies.

(I would say that false cause is a presumption fallacy, because the arguer illegitimately presumes that the given correlation is sufficient to prove the causal connection he wants to make.)


Red Herring

The "inconvenient fact" method of attacking causal arguments doesn't always work. Sometimes the fact in question isn't even remotely inconvenient for the argument. When this happens, the person attacking the argument has committed a red herring fallacy.

Suppose that the "Hacking Cough" study is a long-term study comparing a group of heavy cigarette smokers to a group of nonsmokers has found that, over time, cases of lung cancer crop up in the smoking group at a rate five times that which they crop up in the non-smoking group. Some people take the Hacking Cough Study to have proved that cigarette smoking causes lung cancer. Other people claim that it doesn't prove that cigarette smoking causes lung cancer. If we pretend that these people give the following arguments, we would be pretending that they all commit red herring fallacies, because all the following arguments are red herrings.

The Hacking Cough Study doesn't prove that smoking causes lung cancer because it is a fact that some people who smoke heavily never get lung cancer.

You cannot claim that the Hacking Cough Study proves that smoking causes lung cancer because no one, including the authors of the study, can explain just how it is that smoking manages to cause lung cancer.

Plenty of nonsmokers get lung cancer, so it can't be true that cigarette smoking causes lung cancer.


The first argument is a fallacy because the statement "A causes B" only means "A raises the probability that B will happen," not "A always makes B happen." The second one is a fallacy because causal arguments don't have to provide explanations. Strong evidence of a strong correlation always establishes a cause and effect relationship, whether or not we can explain that relationship. And finally, the third argument is also a red herring because the study doesn't have to prove that smoking is the only cause of lung cancer in order to prove that it is a cause of lung cancer.


Begging the Question in a Causal Argument

I want to emphasize very strongly that a mental association is no substitute for actual evidence. Just because two things are associated in your mind, or you think that one thing must cause another, you cannot even begin to have an argument to that effect until you come up with some real facts. To argue that one thing must cause another merely because you think that it must be so is simply to beg the question. Consider the following.

Rylan. Of course welfare causes dependency! It just stands to reason that people on welfare will want to stay on welfare for as long as possible.
Aspen. Are you crazy? I think it stands to reason that people on welfare will want to get off welfare as soon as possible. We can't both be right, so I don't think talking about "stands to reason" tells us anything about welfare.


Notice that Rylan offers his own opinion as evidence. Unsupported by evidence, his claim that his opinion "stands to reason" is nonsense. Things only stand to reason when they are supported by a good argument. Offering one's personal opinion as evidence is not an argument. Aspen, however, has a good argument. Notice that her conclusion is just that arguments like Rylan's can't prove anything. True, her opinion that people on welfare will want to get off welfare as soon as possible is just her opinion, but it is a fact that she holds that opinion, which shows that Rylan's opinion isn't the only one out there, which is enough to show that Rylan's argument is no good. (Generally, people who tell you that something "stands to reason" instead of giving you an argument are simply trying to cover the fact that they have no argument.)


Consistency With Available Evidence

Sometimes people will insist that some causal claim is true even though all the evidence they have implies that it is false. The following is a paraphrase of an actual conversation. (Only the names have been changed.)

Beau. It's obvious that welfare causes dependency, because someone who's getting money without working is going to want to keep on taking it easy.
Issac. You know, I don't think it's fair of you to project your own preferences on other people. What makes you think that people on welfare feel the same way you would in that situation?
Beau. What are you talking about? I wouldn't feel that way! I'd want to get off welfare as soon as possible.
Issac. Oh, sorry. I guess you were basing this on people you know. Still, you shouldn't assume that the people who end up on welfare are like the people in your family, and your other friends and acquaintances.
Beau. Hey! None of my family are like that! None of my friends would want to stay on welfare. In fact, I don't know anyone who would.
Issac. So you're saying that someone who's getting money without working is going to want to keep on taking it easy, even though all of the actual human beings you know about wouldn't want to keep on taking it easy, even if they were getting money without working.
Beau. Now you've got it.

The first point is, of course, that Beau's conclusion is contradicted by all the evidence he has. He's saying that all people are suceptible to being made dependent by welfare even though all of the people he knows lack that suceptibility. The second point to notice is that Beau is not even using the right kind of strategy to establish a causal claim. His first statement is actually a question begging fallacy, since the statement "someone who's getting money without working is going to want to keep on taking it easy" is simply a more general statement of the claim "welfare causes dependency." The two claims are not different enough to make the premise acceptable to anyone who rejected the conclusion. Issac treats Beau's argument as a generalization as a way of getting Beau to admit that he has evidence that contradicts his conclusion. Beau may indeed be generalizing, since he might have an idea in his head of what he thinks a typical welfare recipiant is like, and is generalizing from this imaginary person to real welfare recipients. Of course, imaginary evidence never counts. (Therefore arguments based on imaginary evidence always commit the relevance fallacy of red herring.)


Causal Chains and Slippery Slopes

The fallacy of slippery slope combines a whole string of dubious causal claims. The difference between a slippery slope fallacy and a legitimate causal chain argument is that the legitimate argument depends upon a series of well-established causal relationships while the slippery slope includes at least one dubious or speculative causal claim.

Censoring hardcore pornography will soon lead to censorship of softcore pornography, which in turn will lead to suppression of harmless erotica like swimsuit photos, and that itself will finally cause censorship of nude pictures in medical textbooks.

If you make marijuana legal then it'll be magic mushrooms. If 'shrooms, then speed, and after that, peyote! Then cocaine won't be far behind. Which means crack! And what about heroin? And acid! Then there's angel dust, and finally those designer drugs that make people's heads explode! So if we make marijuana legal, decent people won't be able to sleep for the sound of all the exploding heads.


Would legalizing marijuana cause 'shrooms to become legal? Would legalizing 'shrooms cause speed to become legal? Would legalizing speed cause peyote to become legal? Would legalizing peyote cause crack to become legal? Would legalizing crack cause heroin to become legal? Would legalizing heroin cause angel dust to become legal? Would legalizing angel dust cause designer drugs to become legal? Is there anything about legalizing one drug that makes it impossible, or extremely difficult to avoid legalizing the next drug in the sequence? If there's any point where we can legalize one (relatively harmless) drug without having to legalize the next (more harmful) drug, the causal chain snaps, and the slippery-slope argument fails.

Attention To Detail

Causal reasoning often requires careful attention to detail, and a willingness to follow the evidence wherever it leads. Consider the following problem.

The village of Ferlinghetti has been famous for it's locally produced mineral water for about 150 years. However, the village also has a problem with adult asthma. Many of the town's adults spend much of their time coughing and wheezing. Locals believe that the mineral water reduces or prevents the asthma and have been drinking more and more of it since the asthma problem was first identified in 1852. The asthma problem has grown slowly but steadily worse, with no interruptions, since the early 1850s. Asthma attacks do not get any worse or any better at any particular time of day or time of year. The leading citizens in the town have identified four possible causes of the asthma. A tin mine in the mountains produces runoff, which mixes with the local drinking water. A perfume factory in the next valley produces fumes, which drift over to Ferlinghetti. Farmers in the nearby plain use a special kind of wheat, which releases pollen that is carried into Ferlinghetti by the prevailing winds. Bats from the local woods fly into the town at night to feed on insects, and leave fur and skin flakes that hang in the air for about an hour after they fly through. The tin mine has been in continuous operation at the same level of production since Roman times. The perfume factory was built in 1843, but was completely shut down for both world war one and world war two. The special wheat was introduced in 1840. The local species of bat was discovered and classified in 1845 when local kids found caves containing both the bats and accumulations of bat droppings that proved to be dozens of feet thick. You are a scientist called in to investigate the situation and discover the cause of the asthma problem.

The town mayor argues, "it's the tin mine in the mountains, because that runoff water does get into the local drinking water. It must have started running off in 1852 and the amount of water running off must have gotten larger and larger since then."

The chief of police claims that "the perfume factory has to be the cause. There must be something in the perfume fumes that causes asthma, and they must have been using it continuously since 1852."

The town drunk confides in you that "the wheat must be the cause. They've been growing it continuously since at least 1852, so it's perfectly well correlated."

And the town librarian says "it's the bats! Aaaaaaaaaaagh! They're after me! Keep them away, keep them away! Send for Buffy now!"


Apply careful causal reasoning to the problem. You will find the answe very clear once you write down and organize all the facts given above. We'll discuss this problem in class. (You can print out just this problem if you download ferlinghetti.htm or ferlinghetti.rtf.)


Reasonableness

Another important issue in causal reasoning is the reasonableness of a causal prediction. A causal prediction is a claim that some action that we contemplate taking will have some particular effect. For instance, the claim that invading Iraq will make us more secure is a causal prediction because it holds that if we invade Iraq (as we just did), the foreseeable future will be more secure for us than if we had not invaded Iraq. An opposing causal prediction might be that the invasion will make us less secure. Such predictions can be partially tested by waiting until after the fact and seeing if the claimed effect actually comes to pass. In the case of the Iraqi invasion, for instance, the first prediction would lead one to expect decreased security at airports, fewer terrorist alerts and less money spent on homeland security, whereas the second prediction would lead one to expect at least a continuing high level of security, more terrorist alerts and more money spent on homeland security. But there are two problems. The first is that there may be other factors involved, so that the real effects are hidden. For instance, it may in fact be true that the invasion increases our security, but some other independent factor, (say, the final fruition of a terrorist plot that was begun well before the invasion was announced, or the loss of competent security administrators in a car accident) decreases our security, hiding the gain from the invasion. The second problem is that we need to be able to predict the effects of our actions before we act. We cannot undo an invasion, so we have to be sure of its effects before we go ahead and do it. For this reason, a great deal of causal reasoning is done without the benefit of definitive evidence regarding the particular kind of action contemplated. The best we can do sometimes is to think about what we might reasonably expect to happen based on generally known causal rules, and such thinking, like any thinking, always runs the risk of committing non-causal as well as causal fallacies. So look out for any and all of the fallacies we've learned previously as well as the causal ones.

If you're not already sick of hearing about the subject, here's a little story about causal reasoning: causalstory.htm

Here are some argument pairs to work on.

For this set, click on the name of the person you think gives the weaker argument

Glenn. Studies show that people who dance are five times as likely to have knobby knees as people who don't dance, so dancing causes knobby knees.
Savanah. Hah! That's ridiculous! Don't you know that everyone of those studies recorded a bunch of people who danced around for years and never got knobby knees, so it must be blindingly obvious that dancing doesn't cause knobby knees.

Tobias. We must ban digital cameras immediately! A major 17-country study has shown that people who use digital cameras are 10 times more likely than non-digicam-users to become lawyers, and that the increase in lawyerism in any area is perfectly correlated with the local increase in digicam use. The study has been checked over by 217 experts who all independently certified it as perfectly conducted and demographically appropriate, with absolutely no reason to think that the study might be flawed in any respect. So we must ban digicams before we are buried in lawyers.
Leila. I've seen that study. I've read that study from cover to cover. And I can tell you we don't need to worry. This study fails to prove that digicam use causes lawyerism because it totally fails to explain how digicam use causes lawyerism.

Everett. I've just discovered some disturbing news about Histafix, the new anti-allergy medicine. Did you know that once allergy sufferers start taking it, they almost never stop! Obviously, this means that taking Histafix causes dependence, on Histafix. I just heard that thousands of people are taking Histafix even as we speak, so we should ban it now so that these people can be cured of their dependence on Histafix.
Kiersten. Um, maybe all these people take Histafix because they all have allergies..

Tate. I just found out that exposure to Faux News causes blowhardery. It's been found that the more time people spend watching Faux News Network, the more likely they are to become irrational, fact-avoidant, gratuitously insulting pompous, brain-dead blowhards!
Kelsie. That's rubbish. I know hundreds of blowhards who never watched Faux News, so blowhardery has nothing to do with watching that Fair And Balanced network

Okay, I'm tired of that. Just click on the link for the answer for the following exercises.

A. Mike. Gasolene is flammable, so I don't think it's a good way to put out that fire.
Karley. The need to pour gasoline on the fire has never been so clear. Ever since I started putting gasoline on the fire it's been getting fiercer and fiercer! So obviously, we need to go out and buy a lot more gasoline. (Answer)

B. Barry. I used to think that Reverend Jim was wasting his time with his Pray for Peace campaign, but it's really begun to foster a sense of community in our parish.
Julius. A sense of community is a good thing, but we must set it against the needs of people in other countries. Since Reverend Jim started his Pray-For-Peace campaign, four more wars have started. We must shut down this Pray-For-Peace campaign before even more countries are dragged into war! (Answer)
 
C. Emily. This invasion of Iraq is going to permanently damage America's security. Almost no one in the Muslim world gives any credibility to the Bush administration's pretext for this war, and people are highly unlikely to forgive what they see as an unprovoked attack on the sovereignty of a Muslim country, so we are likely to see a continuing effort to pull off more 9/11-type attacks on American soil.
Donnie. Hold on there! That ain't necessarily so. Remember that Osama bin Laden was originally incensed by the presence of American troops near the holy sites in Saudi Arabia, not by the American attack on Iraq. Osama's network is pretty much gone now, and there's no evidence that any new network has grown up to take its place. You should also remember that Osama was able to create the Al Qaeda network because of all the Islamic fighters that were drawn together by the Afghan war. Nothing since then has concentrated Islamic fighters in that way, so organizing a network like Al Qaeda will be much more difficult now. Finally, if the United States pulls out of Iraq immediately after a representative and independent Iraqi government is in full control of the country, radical Islamicists will no longer be able to portray America as a permanent desecrator of the holy places. (Answer)


Now that you've mastered causal reasoning, you can easily handle the following exercises with hints instead of complete answers.

E. Celine. It seems obvious that religion was a major causal factor in the Indian rebellion of 1857. The Indian people of that time were a mixture of Hindu and Muslim groups, and they are always fighting each other. Add in the British, who were of a third religion, and you have a recipe for disaster.
Ashly. But the British had been taking over India for a hundred years before the rebellion, and both Hindus and Muslims had frequently fought against people of their own religion and for people of the other religion throughout India's history. (Hint)

I. Dillan. I don't think racism was a major factor in the Indian rebellion. It's true that the British were racist, but everybody was racist at that time, and in 1857 the British were one of the more enlightened colonial governments. The fact is, the average Indian peasant was usually better off under the British than he had been under his previous native ruler.
Abigail. The problem with that is that rebellions are generally not organized by peasants. They are organized by people with organizational skills, such as the thousands of people who were government officials under native governments, but who all lost their jobs to Englishmen when the English East India Company took over native states. That exclusion must have caused enormous resentment because it eliminated all possibility of advancement for thousands of educated Indians, and it was entirely due to racism.  (Hint)

K. Wally. If we allow pornography in adult book stores it won't stop there. Soon it will be in the regular book stores, because they're book stores too. Then it will be in the libraries, because they're just bookstores that lend books instead of selling them. Schools have libraries, so it will soon be in the schools too! Well did you know that churches have schools too, so if we allow pornography in adult book stores it won't be long before it's in our churches too! Obviously, pornography should be banned absolutely
Xena. The people who want to ban pornography are mostly the same people who want to ban all discussion of sex. If we cave in on pornography they'll have a precedent to point to, which will make it easier for them to ban things like The Joy of Sex. If they succeed there, they'll go on to other things, like sex education. If we want to preserve free discussion of sexual matters, we should hold the line on pornography. (Hint)

L. Augustus. I really think that the government should put more money into discouraging cellphone use. Cellphones produce microwave radiation, so using a cellphone is literally holding a radiation source right next to your brain. Radiation causes cancer, so it is insane to routinely expose the most important organ in your body to a known carcinogen several times a day. Millions and millions of people use cellphones on a daily basis, so if cellphones cause cancer these people are at a serious risk. We cannot wait for research because waiting could potentially allow thousands of people to contract deadly brain cancers.
Fred. Wait a moment. Cellphones have been around for years and years, so if they caused cancer we would already see a rise in the cancer rates, and this rise would include a correlation between cancer and cellphone use. This is exactly how we found out that cellphone use causes car accidents. There is no rise in the cancer rates, and cancers are not correlated with cellphone use, so cellphone use is not a significant cause of cancer. (Hint)


Homework 6. Identify the weaker arguments in each of the following five argument pairs and name any fallacies committed You can do this exercise on your own lined paper, (if it doesn't have curly edges from ripping it out of a spiral notebook), or you can use Homework 6 Answer Sheet

1. Cullen. I think it's pretty clear that drinking bottled water causes mopery. A recent study has shown that people who drink bottled water are four times as likely to mope around as people who don't drink bottled water.
Sterling. Yes, but the study also showed that there's plenty of people who mope around without ever touching bottled water, so the study doesn't prove that drinking bottled water causes mopery. (Hint)

2. Quentin. I think we should go back to pumping oxygen into that sunken submarine. It would help the sailors.
Elisha. Since we stopped pumping oxygen into that sunken submarine the sailors have gotten sicker and sicker. This is a very serious situation which we must address immediately by making sure that there is absolutely no oxygen in that sunken submarine. (Hint)

3. Tanya. I've just heard some disturbing news. A major recent study just compared two demographically identical groups, one of which listened to classical music a lot, and the other didn't listen to classical music at all. The group of classical music listeners turned out to have a much higher percentage of white-collar criminals than the non listeners, so it looks like listening to classical music causes white-collar crime.
Alfred. I've seen the same study, and I can tell you that it totally fails to prove that classical music causes white-collar crime because nowhere in that study do they even begin to explain how listening to classical music goes about causing that white-collar crime. (Hint)

4. Roland. Statistics show that once people start using a sunscreen, they almost never go back to sunbathing without it. So obviously use of sunscreen makes people dependent on sunscreen. Since it is bad for people to be dependent, we should abolish sunscreen now.
Vilma. Doesn't it occur to you that people continue to need sunscreen because strong sunlight continues to contain dangerous ultraviolet radiation? (Hint)

5. Humberto. It's beginning to look like drinking herbal tea makes people taller. They did a long-term study comparing a million adult herbal tea drinkers with a million adults who never, ever drink that disgusting rubbish. On average, the people in the herbal tea group got three millimeters taller for every year they drank herbal tea, while the demographically equivalent adults in the other group didn't grow at all.
Camila. Herbal tea doesn't make people taller. Plenty of people in that study drank herbal tea for years without getting any taller. (Hint)

Possible Quiz Questions (This ain't homework! Memorize the answers for next class, cuz there will be a quiz.)
i. Are causal arguments required to explain how the purported cause causes the effect? (Hint)
ii. Are causal arguments required to show that the purported cause is the only thing that ever causes the effect? (Hint)
iii. Are causal arguments required to show that the purported cause absolutely always causes the effect? (Hint)
iv. Are causal arguments required to show that the purported cause is at least sometimes correlated with the effect? (Hint)
v. Can a causal argument be based on a "cause" that hasn't been previously proved to exist? (Hint)
vi. Can a causal argument be based only on the fact that the "cause" is always absent whenever the effect is absent? (Hint)
vii. Can a causal argument work if something else is just as strongly correlated with the effect as the purported cause? (Hint)
viii. Can a causal argument be based on anecdotal evidence? (Hint)
ix. Does the "cause" have to have a one-to-one correspondence with the effect? (Hint)
x. Is "it's the only thing I can think of" ever a good causal argument? (Hint)


Copyright © 2006 by Martin C. Young

Next page.

This Site is Proudly Hosted By.
WEBster Computing Services